Prove that a surreal number is born in a finite stage if and only if it is of the form $frac m{2^n}$.











up vote
4
down vote

favorite
3












We define surreal numbers here. My attempt is to first prove this lemma:




Lemma 1. Suppose in the $n$th stage, we have already constructed 2 surreals $a<b$, with no other surreals constructed between them. Then $$2cdot{a|b}=a+b.$$




From this I can quite easily deduce the desired result. So now the difficulty lies in proving the lemma.



I have tried to expand the multiplication, and using the definition that $x=yLeftrightarrow xle y$ and $xge y$. Doing this I get something that, apparently, needs to be further simplified. However, using the definitions of inequalities breaks it up into more and more pieces, and I don't see anywhere that I can use induction. Also, I can't utilize the condition that $a$ and $b$ are 'adjacent'.



Is there a way to prove this lemma? Or am I going in the wrong direction? Any help is appreciated!










share|cite|improve this question




























    up vote
    4
    down vote

    favorite
    3












    We define surreal numbers here. My attempt is to first prove this lemma:




    Lemma 1. Suppose in the $n$th stage, we have already constructed 2 surreals $a<b$, with no other surreals constructed between them. Then $$2cdot{a|b}=a+b.$$




    From this I can quite easily deduce the desired result. So now the difficulty lies in proving the lemma.



    I have tried to expand the multiplication, and using the definition that $x=yLeftrightarrow xle y$ and $xge y$. Doing this I get something that, apparently, needs to be further simplified. However, using the definitions of inequalities breaks it up into more and more pieces, and I don't see anywhere that I can use induction. Also, I can't utilize the condition that $a$ and $b$ are 'adjacent'.



    Is there a way to prove this lemma? Or am I going in the wrong direction? Any help is appreciated!










    share|cite|improve this question


























      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite
      3









      up vote
      4
      down vote

      favorite
      3






      3





      We define surreal numbers here. My attempt is to first prove this lemma:




      Lemma 1. Suppose in the $n$th stage, we have already constructed 2 surreals $a<b$, with no other surreals constructed between them. Then $$2cdot{a|b}=a+b.$$




      From this I can quite easily deduce the desired result. So now the difficulty lies in proving the lemma.



      I have tried to expand the multiplication, and using the definition that $x=yLeftrightarrow xle y$ and $xge y$. Doing this I get something that, apparently, needs to be further simplified. However, using the definitions of inequalities breaks it up into more and more pieces, and I don't see anywhere that I can use induction. Also, I can't utilize the condition that $a$ and $b$ are 'adjacent'.



      Is there a way to prove this lemma? Or am I going in the wrong direction? Any help is appreciated!










      share|cite|improve this question















      We define surreal numbers here. My attempt is to first prove this lemma:




      Lemma 1. Suppose in the $n$th stage, we have already constructed 2 surreals $a<b$, with no other surreals constructed between them. Then $$2cdot{a|b}=a+b.$$




      From this I can quite easily deduce the desired result. So now the difficulty lies in proving the lemma.



      I have tried to expand the multiplication, and using the definition that $x=yLeftrightarrow xle y$ and $xge y$. Doing this I get something that, apparently, needs to be further simplified. However, using the definitions of inequalities breaks it up into more and more pieces, and I don't see anywhere that I can use induction. Also, I can't utilize the condition that $a$ and $b$ are 'adjacent'.



      Is there a way to prove this lemma? Or am I going in the wrong direction? Any help is appreciated!







      induction surreal-numbers






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited yesterday

























      asked yesterday









      Trebor

      47711




      47711






















          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted










          $newcommand{surr}[2]{left{ #1 mathbin{bigvert} #2 right}}$
          Conway's proof of the question in your title in On Numbers and Games is by a different and rather cleverly indirect argument. First, he proves that the surreal numbers form an ordered field. He also proves that any number $surr{a}{b}$ is equal to the simplest number which is greater than $a$ and less than $b$. (where "simplest" means "constructed in the earliest stage"). Then, he proves the following lemma.




          Lemma (Theorem 12 of ONAG): Suppose $x=frac{ell}{2^m}$ for some integer $ell$. Then $x=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$.



          Proof: We use induction on $m$. For $m=0$ this is easy, since $x$ is an integer and so if $xgeq 0$ then $x$ is the simplest number greater than $x-1$ and if $x<0$ then $x$ is the simplest number less than $x+1$.



          Now suppose $m>0$ and we already know the result for $m-1$. Let $z=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$. Using the definition of addition, we find $$2z=z+z=surr{z+x-frac{1}{2^m}}{z+x+frac{1}{2^m}}.$$ By the induction hypothesis, we know that $2x=surr{2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}{2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}$, since $2x=frac{2ell}{2^{m-1}}$. Thus $2x$ is the simplest number between $2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$ and $2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$, and so it is also the simplest number between $z+x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $z+x+frac{1}{2^m}$ since $$2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}< z+x-frac{1}{2^m} < 2x < z+x+frac{1}{2^m}<2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$$ (these inequalities follow from $x-frac{1}{2^m}<z<x+frac{1}{2^m}$). Looking back at our expression for $2z$ above, this shows that $2x=2z$, and hence $x=z$ as desired.




          Given this lemma, it is then straightforward to completely describe what the $n$th stage of the surreal numbers looks like by induction on $n$. Specifically, if $n>0$ then after the $n$th stage the surreal numbers constructed so far are exactly those of the form $pmleft(i+frac{j}{2^k}right)$ for $i,j,kinmathbb{N}$ such that $jleq 2^k$ and $i+k<n$. For the induction step, then, the $(n+1)$st stage will have the same form because every pair of consecutive numbers $a<b$ constructed after the $n$th stage can be written in the form $a=x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $b=x+frac{1}{2^m}$ for some dyadic rational $x$ with denominator $2^m$, and so the new number $surr{a}{b}$ will be $x=frac{a+b}{2}$ by the lemma.





          Let me finish with some observations on your proposed proof strategy in comparison with Conway's. As far as I know, there isn't any nice way to prove your lemma in isolation. The problem is that the assumption that there are no numbers between $a$ and $b$ constructed so far is not easy to use. You can only really make good use of it if you already know exactly what all the surreal numbers constructed up to the $n$th stage look like. So, your lemma needs to not be a separate lemma proved first, but instead embedded in an inductive proof of a description of the $n$th stage so that you can use the induction hypothesis to get a handle on what $a$ and $b$ can be. That's exactly what the argument above does, to reduce your lemma to Conway's lemma.






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
            – Trebor
            yesterday










          • ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
            – Eric Wofsey
            yesterday













          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          });
          });
          }, "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function() {
          var channelOptions = {
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          };
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
          createEditor();
          });
          }
          else {
          createEditor();
          }
          });

          function createEditor() {
          StackExchange.prepareEditor({
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader: {
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          },
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          });


          }
          });














           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2996290%2fprove-that-a-surreal-number-is-born-in-a-finite-stage-if-and-only-if-it-is-of-th%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest
































          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes








          1 Answer
          1






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted










          $newcommand{surr}[2]{left{ #1 mathbin{bigvert} #2 right}}$
          Conway's proof of the question in your title in On Numbers and Games is by a different and rather cleverly indirect argument. First, he proves that the surreal numbers form an ordered field. He also proves that any number $surr{a}{b}$ is equal to the simplest number which is greater than $a$ and less than $b$. (where "simplest" means "constructed in the earliest stage"). Then, he proves the following lemma.




          Lemma (Theorem 12 of ONAG): Suppose $x=frac{ell}{2^m}$ for some integer $ell$. Then $x=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$.



          Proof: We use induction on $m$. For $m=0$ this is easy, since $x$ is an integer and so if $xgeq 0$ then $x$ is the simplest number greater than $x-1$ and if $x<0$ then $x$ is the simplest number less than $x+1$.



          Now suppose $m>0$ and we already know the result for $m-1$. Let $z=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$. Using the definition of addition, we find $$2z=z+z=surr{z+x-frac{1}{2^m}}{z+x+frac{1}{2^m}}.$$ By the induction hypothesis, we know that $2x=surr{2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}{2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}$, since $2x=frac{2ell}{2^{m-1}}$. Thus $2x$ is the simplest number between $2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$ and $2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$, and so it is also the simplest number between $z+x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $z+x+frac{1}{2^m}$ since $$2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}< z+x-frac{1}{2^m} < 2x < z+x+frac{1}{2^m}<2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$$ (these inequalities follow from $x-frac{1}{2^m}<z<x+frac{1}{2^m}$). Looking back at our expression for $2z$ above, this shows that $2x=2z$, and hence $x=z$ as desired.




          Given this lemma, it is then straightforward to completely describe what the $n$th stage of the surreal numbers looks like by induction on $n$. Specifically, if $n>0$ then after the $n$th stage the surreal numbers constructed so far are exactly those of the form $pmleft(i+frac{j}{2^k}right)$ for $i,j,kinmathbb{N}$ such that $jleq 2^k$ and $i+k<n$. For the induction step, then, the $(n+1)$st stage will have the same form because every pair of consecutive numbers $a<b$ constructed after the $n$th stage can be written in the form $a=x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $b=x+frac{1}{2^m}$ for some dyadic rational $x$ with denominator $2^m$, and so the new number $surr{a}{b}$ will be $x=frac{a+b}{2}$ by the lemma.





          Let me finish with some observations on your proposed proof strategy in comparison with Conway's. As far as I know, there isn't any nice way to prove your lemma in isolation. The problem is that the assumption that there are no numbers between $a$ and $b$ constructed so far is not easy to use. You can only really make good use of it if you already know exactly what all the surreal numbers constructed up to the $n$th stage look like. So, your lemma needs to not be a separate lemma proved first, but instead embedded in an inductive proof of a description of the $n$th stage so that you can use the induction hypothesis to get a handle on what $a$ and $b$ can be. That's exactly what the argument above does, to reduce your lemma to Conway's lemma.






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
            – Trebor
            yesterday










          • ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
            – Eric Wofsey
            yesterday

















          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted










          $newcommand{surr}[2]{left{ #1 mathbin{bigvert} #2 right}}$
          Conway's proof of the question in your title in On Numbers and Games is by a different and rather cleverly indirect argument. First, he proves that the surreal numbers form an ordered field. He also proves that any number $surr{a}{b}$ is equal to the simplest number which is greater than $a$ and less than $b$. (where "simplest" means "constructed in the earliest stage"). Then, he proves the following lemma.




          Lemma (Theorem 12 of ONAG): Suppose $x=frac{ell}{2^m}$ for some integer $ell$. Then $x=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$.



          Proof: We use induction on $m$. For $m=0$ this is easy, since $x$ is an integer and so if $xgeq 0$ then $x$ is the simplest number greater than $x-1$ and if $x<0$ then $x$ is the simplest number less than $x+1$.



          Now suppose $m>0$ and we already know the result for $m-1$. Let $z=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$. Using the definition of addition, we find $$2z=z+z=surr{z+x-frac{1}{2^m}}{z+x+frac{1}{2^m}}.$$ By the induction hypothesis, we know that $2x=surr{2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}{2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}$, since $2x=frac{2ell}{2^{m-1}}$. Thus $2x$ is the simplest number between $2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$ and $2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$, and so it is also the simplest number between $z+x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $z+x+frac{1}{2^m}$ since $$2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}< z+x-frac{1}{2^m} < 2x < z+x+frac{1}{2^m}<2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$$ (these inequalities follow from $x-frac{1}{2^m}<z<x+frac{1}{2^m}$). Looking back at our expression for $2z$ above, this shows that $2x=2z$, and hence $x=z$ as desired.




          Given this lemma, it is then straightforward to completely describe what the $n$th stage of the surreal numbers looks like by induction on $n$. Specifically, if $n>0$ then after the $n$th stage the surreal numbers constructed so far are exactly those of the form $pmleft(i+frac{j}{2^k}right)$ for $i,j,kinmathbb{N}$ such that $jleq 2^k$ and $i+k<n$. For the induction step, then, the $(n+1)$st stage will have the same form because every pair of consecutive numbers $a<b$ constructed after the $n$th stage can be written in the form $a=x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $b=x+frac{1}{2^m}$ for some dyadic rational $x$ with denominator $2^m$, and so the new number $surr{a}{b}$ will be $x=frac{a+b}{2}$ by the lemma.





          Let me finish with some observations on your proposed proof strategy in comparison with Conway's. As far as I know, there isn't any nice way to prove your lemma in isolation. The problem is that the assumption that there are no numbers between $a$ and $b$ constructed so far is not easy to use. You can only really make good use of it if you already know exactly what all the surreal numbers constructed up to the $n$th stage look like. So, your lemma needs to not be a separate lemma proved first, but instead embedded in an inductive proof of a description of the $n$th stage so that you can use the induction hypothesis to get a handle on what $a$ and $b$ can be. That's exactly what the argument above does, to reduce your lemma to Conway's lemma.






          share|cite|improve this answer























          • This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
            – Trebor
            yesterday










          • ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
            – Eric Wofsey
            yesterday















          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          4
          down vote



          accepted






          $newcommand{surr}[2]{left{ #1 mathbin{bigvert} #2 right}}$
          Conway's proof of the question in your title in On Numbers and Games is by a different and rather cleverly indirect argument. First, he proves that the surreal numbers form an ordered field. He also proves that any number $surr{a}{b}$ is equal to the simplest number which is greater than $a$ and less than $b$. (where "simplest" means "constructed in the earliest stage"). Then, he proves the following lemma.




          Lemma (Theorem 12 of ONAG): Suppose $x=frac{ell}{2^m}$ for some integer $ell$. Then $x=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$.



          Proof: We use induction on $m$. For $m=0$ this is easy, since $x$ is an integer and so if $xgeq 0$ then $x$ is the simplest number greater than $x-1$ and if $x<0$ then $x$ is the simplest number less than $x+1$.



          Now suppose $m>0$ and we already know the result for $m-1$. Let $z=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$. Using the definition of addition, we find $$2z=z+z=surr{z+x-frac{1}{2^m}}{z+x+frac{1}{2^m}}.$$ By the induction hypothesis, we know that $2x=surr{2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}{2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}$, since $2x=frac{2ell}{2^{m-1}}$. Thus $2x$ is the simplest number between $2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$ and $2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$, and so it is also the simplest number between $z+x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $z+x+frac{1}{2^m}$ since $$2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}< z+x-frac{1}{2^m} < 2x < z+x+frac{1}{2^m}<2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$$ (these inequalities follow from $x-frac{1}{2^m}<z<x+frac{1}{2^m}$). Looking back at our expression for $2z$ above, this shows that $2x=2z$, and hence $x=z$ as desired.




          Given this lemma, it is then straightforward to completely describe what the $n$th stage of the surreal numbers looks like by induction on $n$. Specifically, if $n>0$ then after the $n$th stage the surreal numbers constructed so far are exactly those of the form $pmleft(i+frac{j}{2^k}right)$ for $i,j,kinmathbb{N}$ such that $jleq 2^k$ and $i+k<n$. For the induction step, then, the $(n+1)$st stage will have the same form because every pair of consecutive numbers $a<b$ constructed after the $n$th stage can be written in the form $a=x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $b=x+frac{1}{2^m}$ for some dyadic rational $x$ with denominator $2^m$, and so the new number $surr{a}{b}$ will be $x=frac{a+b}{2}$ by the lemma.





          Let me finish with some observations on your proposed proof strategy in comparison with Conway's. As far as I know, there isn't any nice way to prove your lemma in isolation. The problem is that the assumption that there are no numbers between $a$ and $b$ constructed so far is not easy to use. You can only really make good use of it if you already know exactly what all the surreal numbers constructed up to the $n$th stage look like. So, your lemma needs to not be a separate lemma proved first, but instead embedded in an inductive proof of a description of the $n$th stage so that you can use the induction hypothesis to get a handle on what $a$ and $b$ can be. That's exactly what the argument above does, to reduce your lemma to Conway's lemma.






          share|cite|improve this answer














          $newcommand{surr}[2]{left{ #1 mathbin{bigvert} #2 right}}$
          Conway's proof of the question in your title in On Numbers and Games is by a different and rather cleverly indirect argument. First, he proves that the surreal numbers form an ordered field. He also proves that any number $surr{a}{b}$ is equal to the simplest number which is greater than $a$ and less than $b$. (where "simplest" means "constructed in the earliest stage"). Then, he proves the following lemma.




          Lemma (Theorem 12 of ONAG): Suppose $x=frac{ell}{2^m}$ for some integer $ell$. Then $x=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$.



          Proof: We use induction on $m$. For $m=0$ this is easy, since $x$ is an integer and so if $xgeq 0$ then $x$ is the simplest number greater than $x-1$ and if $x<0$ then $x$ is the simplest number less than $x+1$.



          Now suppose $m>0$ and we already know the result for $m-1$. Let $z=surr{x-frac{1}{2^m}}{x+frac{1}{2^m}}$. Using the definition of addition, we find $$2z=z+z=surr{z+x-frac{1}{2^m}}{z+x+frac{1}{2^m}}.$$ By the induction hypothesis, we know that $2x=surr{2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}{2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}}$, since $2x=frac{2ell}{2^{m-1}}$. Thus $2x$ is the simplest number between $2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$ and $2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$, and so it is also the simplest number between $z+x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $z+x+frac{1}{2^m}$ since $$2x-frac{1}{2^{m-1}}< z+x-frac{1}{2^m} < 2x < z+x+frac{1}{2^m}<2x+frac{1}{2^{m-1}}$$ (these inequalities follow from $x-frac{1}{2^m}<z<x+frac{1}{2^m}$). Looking back at our expression for $2z$ above, this shows that $2x=2z$, and hence $x=z$ as desired.




          Given this lemma, it is then straightforward to completely describe what the $n$th stage of the surreal numbers looks like by induction on $n$. Specifically, if $n>0$ then after the $n$th stage the surreal numbers constructed so far are exactly those of the form $pmleft(i+frac{j}{2^k}right)$ for $i,j,kinmathbb{N}$ such that $jleq 2^k$ and $i+k<n$. For the induction step, then, the $(n+1)$st stage will have the same form because every pair of consecutive numbers $a<b$ constructed after the $n$th stage can be written in the form $a=x-frac{1}{2^m}$ and $b=x+frac{1}{2^m}$ for some dyadic rational $x$ with denominator $2^m$, and so the new number $surr{a}{b}$ will be $x=frac{a+b}{2}$ by the lemma.





          Let me finish with some observations on your proposed proof strategy in comparison with Conway's. As far as I know, there isn't any nice way to prove your lemma in isolation. The problem is that the assumption that there are no numbers between $a$ and $b$ constructed so far is not easy to use. You can only really make good use of it if you already know exactly what all the surreal numbers constructed up to the $n$th stage look like. So, your lemma needs to not be a separate lemma proved first, but instead embedded in an inductive proof of a description of the $n$th stage so that you can use the induction hypothesis to get a handle on what $a$ and $b$ can be. That's exactly what the argument above does, to reduce your lemma to Conway's lemma.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited yesterday

























          answered yesterday









          Eric Wofsey

          174k12201326




          174k12201326












          • This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
            – Trebor
            yesterday










          • ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
            – Eric Wofsey
            yesterday




















          • This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
            – Trebor
            yesterday










          • ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
            – Eric Wofsey
            yesterday


















          This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
          – Trebor
          yesterday




          This is precisely what I wanted. Could you please tell me the complete book name? Thank you so much :)
          – Trebor
          yesterday












          ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
          – Eric Wofsey
          yesterday






          ONAG is On Numbers and Games by John Conway. It's the original monograph by Conway that introduced surreal numbers and combinatorial game theory in its modern formulation.
          – Eric Wofsey
          yesterday




















           

          draft saved


          draft discarded



















































           


          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function () {
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2996290%2fprove-that-a-surreal-number-is-born-in-a-finite-stage-if-and-only-if-it-is-of-th%23new-answer', 'question_page');
          }
          );

          Post as a guest




















































































          Popular posts from this blog

          Probability when a professor distributes a quiz and homework assignment to a class of n students.

          Aardman Animations

          Are they similar matrix