$limlimits_{ntoinfty}fleft(frac{x}{n}right)=0$ for every $x > 0$. Prove $limlimits_{x to 0}f(x)=0$
$begingroup$
Function $f: (0, infty) to mathbb{R}$ is continuous. For every positive $x$ we have $limlimits_{ntoinfty}fleft(frac{x}{n}right)=0$. Prove that $limlimits_{x to 0}f(x)=0$. I have tried to deduce something from definition of continuity, but with no effect.
limits continuity
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Function $f: (0, infty) to mathbb{R}$ is continuous. For every positive $x$ we have $limlimits_{ntoinfty}fleft(frac{x}{n}right)=0$. Prove that $limlimits_{x to 0}f(x)=0$. I have tried to deduce something from definition of continuity, but with no effect.
limits continuity
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Function $f: (0, infty) to mathbb{R}$ is continuous. For every positive $x$ we have $limlimits_{ntoinfty}fleft(frac{x}{n}right)=0$. Prove that $limlimits_{x to 0}f(x)=0$. I have tried to deduce something from definition of continuity, but with no effect.
limits continuity
$endgroup$
Function $f: (0, infty) to mathbb{R}$ is continuous. For every positive $x$ we have $limlimits_{ntoinfty}fleft(frac{x}{n}right)=0$. Prove that $limlimits_{x to 0}f(x)=0$. I have tried to deduce something from definition of continuity, but with no effect.
limits continuity
limits continuity
edited Jan 7 at 22:40
rtybase
11.6k31534
11.6k31534
asked Jan 7 at 22:20
user4201961user4201961
725411
725411
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59
add a comment |
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59
add a comment |
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
The proof relies on the following lemma:
Let $I subset (0,infty)$ be a closed bounded interval. Let $U subset (0,infty)$ be an open subset accumulating at $0$. Then there exists some integer $N geq 2$ and some closed interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Sketch of proof: take some $x in U$ with $x$ lower than the length of $I$ and the minimum of $I$ . For some integer $N geq 2$, $Nx in overset{circ}{I}$, thus, there exists some compact interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Now, assume $f$ does not go to $0$ at $0$. Then, for some $epsilon > 0$, $U={|f| > epsilon}$ is an open subset of $(0,infty)$ accumulating at $0$.
By iterating the lemma, we can construct sequences of compact intervals $(I_n)$ and integers $(N_n)$ such that $N_{n+1}I_{n+1} subset I_{n-1}$, $N_n geq 2$.
Now, let $A_n=N_1 ldots N_n$, then $A_n rightarrow infty$ and $K_n=A_n cdot I_n$ is a non-increasing sequence of nonempty compact intervals in $I_0$. Thus, there exists $x$ that is in every $K_n$.
So, $x/A_n in I_n subset U$, for all $n$, thus $|f(x/A_n)| > epsilon$ for all $n$, a contradiction.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is a standard application of Baire Category Theorem (BCT). Since $(0,infty)=cup_n {x:|f(frac x k)| leqepsilon ,forall k leq n}$ there exists $n$ such that ${x:|f(frac x k)| leq epsilon , forall k geq n}$ contains some open interval $(a,b)$. [ Because $(0,infty)$, being an open subset of $mathbb R$ has an equivalent complete metric so BCT applies]. This gives UNIFORM convergence of $f(frac x n)$ to $0$ on some open interval from which the result follows easily. [ Details: let $0<delta <b-a$ and $delta < frac a n$. Then, for any $x <delta $ the interval $(frac a x,frac b x)$ has length exceeding $1$, so it contains an interger $k$. Hence $kx in (a,b)$. Also, $k >frac a x > frac a {delta} > n$ so $|f(x)|=|f(frac {kx} k)| <epsilon$].
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3065572%2flim-limits-n-to-inftyf-left-fracxn-right-0-for-every-x-0-prove%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
The proof relies on the following lemma:
Let $I subset (0,infty)$ be a closed bounded interval. Let $U subset (0,infty)$ be an open subset accumulating at $0$. Then there exists some integer $N geq 2$ and some closed interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Sketch of proof: take some $x in U$ with $x$ lower than the length of $I$ and the minimum of $I$ . For some integer $N geq 2$, $Nx in overset{circ}{I}$, thus, there exists some compact interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Now, assume $f$ does not go to $0$ at $0$. Then, for some $epsilon > 0$, $U={|f| > epsilon}$ is an open subset of $(0,infty)$ accumulating at $0$.
By iterating the lemma, we can construct sequences of compact intervals $(I_n)$ and integers $(N_n)$ such that $N_{n+1}I_{n+1} subset I_{n-1}$, $N_n geq 2$.
Now, let $A_n=N_1 ldots N_n$, then $A_n rightarrow infty$ and $K_n=A_n cdot I_n$ is a non-increasing sequence of nonempty compact intervals in $I_0$. Thus, there exists $x$ that is in every $K_n$.
So, $x/A_n in I_n subset U$, for all $n$, thus $|f(x/A_n)| > epsilon$ for all $n$, a contradiction.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The proof relies on the following lemma:
Let $I subset (0,infty)$ be a closed bounded interval. Let $U subset (0,infty)$ be an open subset accumulating at $0$. Then there exists some integer $N geq 2$ and some closed interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Sketch of proof: take some $x in U$ with $x$ lower than the length of $I$ and the minimum of $I$ . For some integer $N geq 2$, $Nx in overset{circ}{I}$, thus, there exists some compact interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Now, assume $f$ does not go to $0$ at $0$. Then, for some $epsilon > 0$, $U={|f| > epsilon}$ is an open subset of $(0,infty)$ accumulating at $0$.
By iterating the lemma, we can construct sequences of compact intervals $(I_n)$ and integers $(N_n)$ such that $N_{n+1}I_{n+1} subset I_{n-1}$, $N_n geq 2$.
Now, let $A_n=N_1 ldots N_n$, then $A_n rightarrow infty$ and $K_n=A_n cdot I_n$ is a non-increasing sequence of nonempty compact intervals in $I_0$. Thus, there exists $x$ that is in every $K_n$.
So, $x/A_n in I_n subset U$, for all $n$, thus $|f(x/A_n)| > epsilon$ for all $n$, a contradiction.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The proof relies on the following lemma:
Let $I subset (0,infty)$ be a closed bounded interval. Let $U subset (0,infty)$ be an open subset accumulating at $0$. Then there exists some integer $N geq 2$ and some closed interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Sketch of proof: take some $x in U$ with $x$ lower than the length of $I$ and the minimum of $I$ . For some integer $N geq 2$, $Nx in overset{circ}{I}$, thus, there exists some compact interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Now, assume $f$ does not go to $0$ at $0$. Then, for some $epsilon > 0$, $U={|f| > epsilon}$ is an open subset of $(0,infty)$ accumulating at $0$.
By iterating the lemma, we can construct sequences of compact intervals $(I_n)$ and integers $(N_n)$ such that $N_{n+1}I_{n+1} subset I_{n-1}$, $N_n geq 2$.
Now, let $A_n=N_1 ldots N_n$, then $A_n rightarrow infty$ and $K_n=A_n cdot I_n$ is a non-increasing sequence of nonempty compact intervals in $I_0$. Thus, there exists $x$ that is in every $K_n$.
So, $x/A_n in I_n subset U$, for all $n$, thus $|f(x/A_n)| > epsilon$ for all $n$, a contradiction.
$endgroup$
The proof relies on the following lemma:
Let $I subset (0,infty)$ be a closed bounded interval. Let $U subset (0,infty)$ be an open subset accumulating at $0$. Then there exists some integer $N geq 2$ and some closed interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Sketch of proof: take some $x in U$ with $x$ lower than the length of $I$ and the minimum of $I$ . For some integer $N geq 2$, $Nx in overset{circ}{I}$, thus, there exists some compact interval $J subset U$ such that $N cdot J subset I$.
Now, assume $f$ does not go to $0$ at $0$. Then, for some $epsilon > 0$, $U={|f| > epsilon}$ is an open subset of $(0,infty)$ accumulating at $0$.
By iterating the lemma, we can construct sequences of compact intervals $(I_n)$ and integers $(N_n)$ such that $N_{n+1}I_{n+1} subset I_{n-1}$, $N_n geq 2$.
Now, let $A_n=N_1 ldots N_n$, then $A_n rightarrow infty$ and $K_n=A_n cdot I_n$ is a non-increasing sequence of nonempty compact intervals in $I_0$. Thus, there exists $x$ that is in every $K_n$.
So, $x/A_n in I_n subset U$, for all $n$, thus $|f(x/A_n)| > epsilon$ for all $n$, a contradiction.
edited Jan 8 at 0:00
answered Jan 7 at 22:50
MindlackMindlack
4,910211
4,910211
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
(edited) This looks correct, but I think you can remove some of the intermediate claims without affecting the argument. In particular, you don't need any information about $sup I_n$. Also, when you say the sequence $K_n$ is non-decreasing, I think you mean that it is decreasing, or in more familiar language, descending. And in the final sentence, "all $n$" should be "infinitely many $n$".
$endgroup$
– Chris Culter
Jan 7 at 23:41
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Thanks for the remarks, I edited. However, in the last sentence, I definitely meant « for all $n$ » and not « for infinitely many $n$», however this does not affect the result.
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:02
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
$begingroup$
Reminds me of the Axiom of Archimedes.
$endgroup$
– marty cohen
Jan 8 at 0:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is a standard application of Baire Category Theorem (BCT). Since $(0,infty)=cup_n {x:|f(frac x k)| leqepsilon ,forall k leq n}$ there exists $n$ such that ${x:|f(frac x k)| leq epsilon , forall k geq n}$ contains some open interval $(a,b)$. [ Because $(0,infty)$, being an open subset of $mathbb R$ has an equivalent complete metric so BCT applies]. This gives UNIFORM convergence of $f(frac x n)$ to $0$ on some open interval from which the result follows easily. [ Details: let $0<delta <b-a$ and $delta < frac a n$. Then, for any $x <delta $ the interval $(frac a x,frac b x)$ has length exceeding $1$, so it contains an interger $k$. Hence $kx in (a,b)$. Also, $k >frac a x > frac a {delta} > n$ so $|f(x)|=|f(frac {kx} k)| <epsilon$].
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is a standard application of Baire Category Theorem (BCT). Since $(0,infty)=cup_n {x:|f(frac x k)| leqepsilon ,forall k leq n}$ there exists $n$ such that ${x:|f(frac x k)| leq epsilon , forall k geq n}$ contains some open interval $(a,b)$. [ Because $(0,infty)$, being an open subset of $mathbb R$ has an equivalent complete metric so BCT applies]. This gives UNIFORM convergence of $f(frac x n)$ to $0$ on some open interval from which the result follows easily. [ Details: let $0<delta <b-a$ and $delta < frac a n$. Then, for any $x <delta $ the interval $(frac a x,frac b x)$ has length exceeding $1$, so it contains an interger $k$. Hence $kx in (a,b)$. Also, $k >frac a x > frac a {delta} > n$ so $|f(x)|=|f(frac {kx} k)| <epsilon$].
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
add a comment |
$begingroup$
This is a standard application of Baire Category Theorem (BCT). Since $(0,infty)=cup_n {x:|f(frac x k)| leqepsilon ,forall k leq n}$ there exists $n$ such that ${x:|f(frac x k)| leq epsilon , forall k geq n}$ contains some open interval $(a,b)$. [ Because $(0,infty)$, being an open subset of $mathbb R$ has an equivalent complete metric so BCT applies]. This gives UNIFORM convergence of $f(frac x n)$ to $0$ on some open interval from which the result follows easily. [ Details: let $0<delta <b-a$ and $delta < frac a n$. Then, for any $x <delta $ the interval $(frac a x,frac b x)$ has length exceeding $1$, so it contains an interger $k$. Hence $kx in (a,b)$. Also, $k >frac a x > frac a {delta} > n$ so $|f(x)|=|f(frac {kx} k)| <epsilon$].
$endgroup$
This is a standard application of Baire Category Theorem (BCT). Since $(0,infty)=cup_n {x:|f(frac x k)| leqepsilon ,forall k leq n}$ there exists $n$ such that ${x:|f(frac x k)| leq epsilon , forall k geq n}$ contains some open interval $(a,b)$. [ Because $(0,infty)$, being an open subset of $mathbb R$ has an equivalent complete metric so BCT applies]. This gives UNIFORM convergence of $f(frac x n)$ to $0$ on some open interval from which the result follows easily. [ Details: let $0<delta <b-a$ and $delta < frac a n$. Then, for any $x <delta $ the interval $(frac a x,frac b x)$ has length exceeding $1$, so it contains an interger $k$. Hence $kx in (a,b)$. Also, $k >frac a x > frac a {delta} > n$ so $|f(x)|=|f(frac {kx} k)| <epsilon$].
edited Jan 8 at 5:13
answered Jan 8 at 0:14
Kavi Rama MurthyKavi Rama Murthy
74.4k53270
74.4k53270
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
Shouldn’t it be $bigcup_n{x,,forall kgeq n,, |f(x/k)| leq epsilon}$?
$endgroup$
– Mindlack
Jan 8 at 0:54
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
$begingroup$
@Mindlack You are right. That was a silly mistake I made.
$endgroup$
– Kavi Rama Murthy
Jan 8 at 5:01
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3065572%2flim-limits-n-to-inftyf-left-fracxn-right-0-for-every-x-0-prove%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
What level course is this for? To me this is the kind of question that seems like a Baire Category Theorem thing.
$endgroup$
– Moya
Jan 7 at 22:41
$begingroup$
$n$ is an integer?
$endgroup$
– leonbloy
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
But can you just not rewrite the limit such that $y=frac{x}{n}$ and so you get what you need by letting $y$ going to 0, which does happen as $n$ goes to infinity and $x$ is any positive real and f is continuous of course so the limit exists?
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:46
$begingroup$
@Moya introductory level
$endgroup$
– user4201961
Jan 7 at 22:48
$begingroup$
This I believe is just a bit more general than the following, you can proceed in a similar manner math.stackexchange.com/questions/3045776/…
$endgroup$
– Marco Bellocchi
Jan 7 at 22:59