Soft Question - Definition of the Real Plane












3












$begingroup$


I have only seen the real plane to be defined as $mathbb R times mathbb R$.



In Euclidean geometry, the origin does not play any central role, but in this set theoretic definition, it does. Is there a way to define the real plane in a way that does not give any special importance to the origin, that is, is there a way to defined the real plane without using coordinates (or products)?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    $(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
    $endgroup$
    – Emilio Novati
    Dec 6 '18 at 21:17










  • $begingroup$
    What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:57


















3












$begingroup$


I have only seen the real plane to be defined as $mathbb R times mathbb R$.



In Euclidean geometry, the origin does not play any central role, but in this set theoretic definition, it does. Is there a way to define the real plane in a way that does not give any special importance to the origin, that is, is there a way to defined the real plane without using coordinates (or products)?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    $(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
    $endgroup$
    – Emilio Novati
    Dec 6 '18 at 21:17










  • $begingroup$
    What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:57
















3












3








3


3



$begingroup$


I have only seen the real plane to be defined as $mathbb R times mathbb R$.



In Euclidean geometry, the origin does not play any central role, but in this set theoretic definition, it does. Is there a way to define the real plane in a way that does not give any special importance to the origin, that is, is there a way to defined the real plane without using coordinates (or products)?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




I have only seen the real plane to be defined as $mathbb R times mathbb R$.



In Euclidean geometry, the origin does not play any central role, but in this set theoretic definition, it does. Is there a way to define the real plane in a way that does not give any special importance to the origin, that is, is there a way to defined the real plane without using coordinates (or products)?







linear-algebra geometry euclidean-geometry






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Dec 6 '18 at 22:30







LinearGuy

















asked Dec 6 '18 at 21:07









LinearGuyLinearGuy

13711




13711








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    $(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
    $endgroup$
    – Emilio Novati
    Dec 6 '18 at 21:17










  • $begingroup$
    What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:57
















  • 2




    $begingroup$
    $(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
    $endgroup$
    – Emilio Novati
    Dec 6 '18 at 21:17










  • $begingroup$
    What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:57










2




2




$begingroup$
$(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
$endgroup$
– Emilio Novati
Dec 6 '18 at 21:17




$begingroup$
$(0,0)$ is a couple as all others elements of $mathbb{R}times mathbb{R}$. Why you say that this couple play a special rule?
$endgroup$
– Emilio Novati
Dec 6 '18 at 21:17












$begingroup$
What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Dec 10 '18 at 19:57






$begingroup$
What axioms are you willing to start from? From your question, and from your comments to the various answers, it appears that you are not willing to start from the axioms of the real numbers, nor are you willing to start from the axioms of Euclidean geometry, both of which are fully rigorous axiomatic systems from the modern mathematical point of view. All of modern mathematics starts from some axiomatic system. So, what axiomatic system are you willing to start from?
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Dec 10 '18 at 19:57












3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















3












$begingroup$

Euclid never defined the plane in his elements, and indeed never used numbers to measure length, angles, or area. In this sense, the Euclidean plane is not the same as the Cartesian plane. Euclid used a plane to mean a flat, two-dimensional surface that extends infinitely far, independent of numerical values. This definition gives no importance to the origin, as indeed there is no origin.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:14










  • $begingroup$
    Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:54



















3












$begingroup$

I think what you are interested in is exactly the difference between an affine space and a vector space. Read the first few paragraphs in that wikipedia article. Basically, you get rid of the "specialness of the origin" by thinking of two copies of the plane. One represents the group, $G$, of translations and the second is the geometric manifold, $X$, that represents your space. For any two points $x$ and $y$ in your space $X$, there is a unique translation $g$ in $G$ that takes $x$ to $y$. Thus, seen in this way, there are no "special" points in $X$. Notice that the origin is special in $G$ since it represents the identity translation, i.e. the one that keeps $X$ fixed. An even more general concept is that of a principal homogenous space.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:17












  • $begingroup$
    OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
    $endgroup$
    – zoidberg
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:22












  • $begingroup$
    @LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:24












  • $begingroup$
    Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
    $endgroup$
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:43



















1












$begingroup$


Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert
in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie



Hilbert's axiom system is constructed with six primitive notions:
three primitive terms:[5]



point;
line;
plane;


and three primitive relations:[6]



Betweenness, a ternary relation linking points;
Lies on (Containment), three binary relations, one linking points and straight lines, one linking points and planes, and one linking


straight lines and planes;
Congruence, two binary relations, one linking line segments and one linking angles, each denoted by an infix ≅.



Line segments, angles, and triangles may each be defined in terms of
points and straight lines, using the relations of betweenness and
containment.[how?] All points, straight lines, and planes in the
following axioms are distinct unless otherwise stated.




https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:38












  • $begingroup$
    The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    Dec 7 '18 at 0:43











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3029051%2fsoft-question-definition-of-the-real-plane%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes








3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









3












$begingroup$

Euclid never defined the plane in his elements, and indeed never used numbers to measure length, angles, or area. In this sense, the Euclidean plane is not the same as the Cartesian plane. Euclid used a plane to mean a flat, two-dimensional surface that extends infinitely far, independent of numerical values. This definition gives no importance to the origin, as indeed there is no origin.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:14










  • $begingroup$
    Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:54
















3












$begingroup$

Euclid never defined the plane in his elements, and indeed never used numbers to measure length, angles, or area. In this sense, the Euclidean plane is not the same as the Cartesian plane. Euclid used a plane to mean a flat, two-dimensional surface that extends infinitely far, independent of numerical values. This definition gives no importance to the origin, as indeed there is no origin.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:14










  • $begingroup$
    Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:54














3












3








3





$begingroup$

Euclid never defined the plane in his elements, and indeed never used numbers to measure length, angles, or area. In this sense, the Euclidean plane is not the same as the Cartesian plane. Euclid used a plane to mean a flat, two-dimensional surface that extends infinitely far, independent of numerical values. This definition gives no importance to the origin, as indeed there is no origin.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



Euclid never defined the plane in his elements, and indeed never used numbers to measure length, angles, or area. In this sense, the Euclidean plane is not the same as the Cartesian plane. Euclid used a plane to mean a flat, two-dimensional surface that extends infinitely far, independent of numerical values. This definition gives no importance to the origin, as indeed there is no origin.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Dec 6 '18 at 21:54









shipwaymgshipwaymg

311




311












  • $begingroup$
    The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:14










  • $begingroup$
    Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:54


















  • $begingroup$
    The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:14










  • $begingroup$
    Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
    $endgroup$
    – Lee Mosher
    Dec 10 '18 at 19:54
















$begingroup$
The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:14




$begingroup$
The type of this defintion that Euclid used is what I am looking for, except I am looking for a defintion that has actually mathematical meaning rather than just intuitive meaning.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:14












$begingroup$
Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Dec 10 '18 at 19:54




$begingroup$
Euclid's axioms and definitions do indeed have mathematical meaning. This was first shown, with full (modern) mathematical rigor, by Hilbert. If you want to see a recent treatment of Euclid to be convinced of this, one good place to start is the book by Hartshorne, "Geometry: Euclid and beyond".
$endgroup$
– Lee Mosher
Dec 10 '18 at 19:54











3












$begingroup$

I think what you are interested in is exactly the difference between an affine space and a vector space. Read the first few paragraphs in that wikipedia article. Basically, you get rid of the "specialness of the origin" by thinking of two copies of the plane. One represents the group, $G$, of translations and the second is the geometric manifold, $X$, that represents your space. For any two points $x$ and $y$ in your space $X$, there is a unique translation $g$ in $G$ that takes $x$ to $y$. Thus, seen in this way, there are no "special" points in $X$. Notice that the origin is special in $G$ since it represents the identity translation, i.e. the one that keeps $X$ fixed. An even more general concept is that of a principal homogenous space.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:17












  • $begingroup$
    OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
    $endgroup$
    – zoidberg
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:22












  • $begingroup$
    @LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:24












  • $begingroup$
    Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
    $endgroup$
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:43
















3












$begingroup$

I think what you are interested in is exactly the difference between an affine space and a vector space. Read the first few paragraphs in that wikipedia article. Basically, you get rid of the "specialness of the origin" by thinking of two copies of the plane. One represents the group, $G$, of translations and the second is the geometric manifold, $X$, that represents your space. For any two points $x$ and $y$ in your space $X$, there is a unique translation $g$ in $G$ that takes $x$ to $y$. Thus, seen in this way, there are no "special" points in $X$. Notice that the origin is special in $G$ since it represents the identity translation, i.e. the one that keeps $X$ fixed. An even more general concept is that of a principal homogenous space.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:17












  • $begingroup$
    OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
    $endgroup$
    – zoidberg
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:22












  • $begingroup$
    @LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:24












  • $begingroup$
    Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
    $endgroup$
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:43














3












3








3





$begingroup$

I think what you are interested in is exactly the difference between an affine space and a vector space. Read the first few paragraphs in that wikipedia article. Basically, you get rid of the "specialness of the origin" by thinking of two copies of the plane. One represents the group, $G$, of translations and the second is the geometric manifold, $X$, that represents your space. For any two points $x$ and $y$ in your space $X$, there is a unique translation $g$ in $G$ that takes $x$ to $y$. Thus, seen in this way, there are no "special" points in $X$. Notice that the origin is special in $G$ since it represents the identity translation, i.e. the one that keeps $X$ fixed. An even more general concept is that of a principal homogenous space.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$



I think what you are interested in is exactly the difference between an affine space and a vector space. Read the first few paragraphs in that wikipedia article. Basically, you get rid of the "specialness of the origin" by thinking of two copies of the plane. One represents the group, $G$, of translations and the second is the geometric manifold, $X$, that represents your space. For any two points $x$ and $y$ in your space $X$, there is a unique translation $g$ in $G$ that takes $x$ to $y$. Thus, seen in this way, there are no "special" points in $X$. Notice that the origin is special in $G$ since it represents the identity translation, i.e. the one that keeps $X$ fixed. An even more general concept is that of a principal homogenous space.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Dec 6 '18 at 22:13









zoidbergzoidberg

1,065113




1,065113












  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:17












  • $begingroup$
    OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
    $endgroup$
    – zoidberg
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:22












  • $begingroup$
    @LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:24












  • $begingroup$
    Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
    $endgroup$
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:43


















  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:17












  • $begingroup$
    OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
    $endgroup$
    – zoidberg
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:22












  • $begingroup$
    @LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:24












  • $begingroup$
    Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
    $endgroup$
    – Daniel Schepler
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:43
















$begingroup$
Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:17






$begingroup$
Yes, I am more or less looking for a defintion that resembles and affine space, but, as far as I know, one still uses $mathbb R times mathbb R$ and then lets the group act on it.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:17














$begingroup$
OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
$endgroup$
– zoidberg
Dec 6 '18 at 22:22






$begingroup$
OK, well if you already know what an affine space is, I don't know what else can satisfy you. In general, I think it's difficult to define specific "non-special things" since the very act of defining it privileges some choice. The way to get at the "generic" is by looking at all the possibilities at once. For instance, how do you get rid of the special "north pole" point on a sphere? By imagining the set of all rotations you can perform on it, i.e. all the symmetries.
$endgroup$
– zoidberg
Dec 6 '18 at 22:22














$begingroup$
@LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
$endgroup$
– David K
Dec 6 '18 at 22:24






$begingroup$
@LinearGuy As far as I can see, the group $G$ is isomorphic to $mathbb Rtimesmathbb R$ but there is no need for $X$ to have intrinsic coordinates. Of course, once you declare that some point in $X$ has coordinates $(x_1,x_2)$ then all the points have coordinates and exactly one has coordinates $(0,0)$--so don't do that.
$endgroup$
– David K
Dec 6 '18 at 22:24














$begingroup$
Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 6 '18 at 22:43




$begingroup$
Furthermore, by viewing $mathbb{R} times mathbb{R}$ as a vector space (and often as an oriented inner product space) you get rid of the "specialness" of vectors pointing "along the $x$-axis or along the $y$-axis" since then no one (orthonormal) basis of $mathbb{R}^2$ is any better than another. This would reflect the isotropy (direction independence / rotation invariance) of Euclidean-style geometry, just as passing to the affine space reflects the homogeneity (location independence / translation invariance).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Schepler
Dec 6 '18 at 22:43











1












$begingroup$


Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert
in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie



Hilbert's axiom system is constructed with six primitive notions:
three primitive terms:[5]



point;
line;
plane;


and three primitive relations:[6]



Betweenness, a ternary relation linking points;
Lies on (Containment), three binary relations, one linking points and straight lines, one linking points and planes, and one linking


straight lines and planes;
Congruence, two binary relations, one linking line segments and one linking angles, each denoted by an infix ≅.



Line segments, angles, and triangles may each be defined in terms of
points and straight lines, using the relations of betweenness and
containment.[how?] All points, straight lines, and planes in the
following axioms are distinct unless otherwise stated.




https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:38












  • $begingroup$
    The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    Dec 7 '18 at 0:43
















1












$begingroup$


Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert
in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie



Hilbert's axiom system is constructed with six primitive notions:
three primitive terms:[5]



point;
line;
plane;


and three primitive relations:[6]



Betweenness, a ternary relation linking points;
Lies on (Containment), three binary relations, one linking points and straight lines, one linking points and planes, and one linking


straight lines and planes;
Congruence, two binary relations, one linking line segments and one linking angles, each denoted by an infix ≅.



Line segments, angles, and triangles may each be defined in terms of
points and straight lines, using the relations of betweenness and
containment.[how?] All points, straight lines, and planes in the
following axioms are distinct unless otherwise stated.




https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:38












  • $begingroup$
    The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    Dec 7 '18 at 0:43














1












1








1





$begingroup$


Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert
in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie



Hilbert's axiom system is constructed with six primitive notions:
three primitive terms:[5]



point;
line;
plane;


and three primitive relations:[6]



Betweenness, a ternary relation linking points;
Lies on (Containment), three binary relations, one linking points and straight lines, one linking points and planes, and one linking


straight lines and planes;
Congruence, two binary relations, one linking line segments and one linking angles, each denoted by an infix ≅.



Line segments, angles, and triangles may each be defined in terms of
points and straight lines, using the relations of betweenness and
containment.[how?] All points, straight lines, and planes in the
following axioms are distinct unless otherwise stated.




https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$




Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 assumptions proposed by David Hilbert
in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie



Hilbert's axiom system is constructed with six primitive notions:
three primitive terms:[5]



point;
line;
plane;


and three primitive relations:[6]



Betweenness, a ternary relation linking points;
Lies on (Containment), three binary relations, one linking points and straight lines, one linking points and planes, and one linking


straight lines and planes;
Congruence, two binary relations, one linking line segments and one linking angles, each denoted by an infix ≅.



Line segments, angles, and triangles may each be defined in terms of
points and straight lines, using the relations of betweenness and
containment.[how?] All points, straight lines, and planes in the
following axioms are distinct unless otherwise stated.




https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_axioms







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered Dec 6 '18 at 22:35









Ethan BolkerEthan Bolker

42.4k549112




42.4k549112












  • $begingroup$
    Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:38












  • $begingroup$
    The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    Dec 7 '18 at 0:43


















  • $begingroup$
    Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
    $endgroup$
    – LinearGuy
    Dec 6 '18 at 22:38












  • $begingroup$
    The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
    $endgroup$
    – Ethan Bolker
    Dec 7 '18 at 0:43
















$begingroup$
Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:38






$begingroup$
Yes, but he never defined the plane and only uses the intuition of it.
$endgroup$
– LinearGuy
Dec 6 '18 at 22:38














$begingroup$
The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
Dec 7 '18 at 0:43




$begingroup$
The lines and points are the plane. With these axioms you can derive all the things Euclid proved, with no appeal to intuition, except to guess what you will be able to prove.
$endgroup$
– Ethan Bolker
Dec 7 '18 at 0:43


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3029051%2fsoft-question-definition-of-the-real-plane%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Probability when a professor distributes a quiz and homework assignment to a class of n students.

Aardman Animations

Are they similar matrix