Probably true, but provably unprovable











up vote
28
down vote

favorite
8












I'm wondering if anyone has found, or can find, a sequence of statements $P(n)$ ($n in mathbb{N}$) such that:




  1. Heuristic arguments using probability theory suggest that all the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  2. One can prove, preferably by making the probabilistic arguments rigorous, that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  3. One can prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable (say in Peano arithmetic or ZFC).



The goal here would be to find statements that are true 'just because they are probably true', not because we can put our finger on a reason why any individual one must be true.



An example of such a sequence of statements might be 'if $p_n$ is the $n$th prime, there are infinitely many repunit primes in base $p_n$'. However while this example meets condition 1 we seem far from having enough understanding of mathematics to prove 2, and 3 seems hopeless. I think we need a less charismatic sequence of statements that are more carefully crafted to the task at hand.










share|cite|improve this question




















  • 5




    It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
    – James Hanson
    Nov 16 at 17:19






  • 3




    What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
    – YCor
    Nov 16 at 18:13






  • 1




    Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
    – Ilya Bogdanov
    Nov 16 at 19:37








  • 1




    How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
    – Nik Weaver
    Nov 16 at 20:53






  • 3




    The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
    – John Baez
    Nov 16 at 22:11















up vote
28
down vote

favorite
8












I'm wondering if anyone has found, or can find, a sequence of statements $P(n)$ ($n in mathbb{N}$) such that:




  1. Heuristic arguments using probability theory suggest that all the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  2. One can prove, preferably by making the probabilistic arguments rigorous, that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  3. One can prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable (say in Peano arithmetic or ZFC).



The goal here would be to find statements that are true 'just because they are probably true', not because we can put our finger on a reason why any individual one must be true.



An example of such a sequence of statements might be 'if $p_n$ is the $n$th prime, there are infinitely many repunit primes in base $p_n$'. However while this example meets condition 1 we seem far from having enough understanding of mathematics to prove 2, and 3 seems hopeless. I think we need a less charismatic sequence of statements that are more carefully crafted to the task at hand.










share|cite|improve this question




















  • 5




    It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
    – James Hanson
    Nov 16 at 17:19






  • 3




    What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
    – YCor
    Nov 16 at 18:13






  • 1




    Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
    – Ilya Bogdanov
    Nov 16 at 19:37








  • 1




    How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
    – Nik Weaver
    Nov 16 at 20:53






  • 3




    The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
    – John Baez
    Nov 16 at 22:11













up vote
28
down vote

favorite
8









up vote
28
down vote

favorite
8






8





I'm wondering if anyone has found, or can find, a sequence of statements $P(n)$ ($n in mathbb{N}$) such that:




  1. Heuristic arguments using probability theory suggest that all the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  2. One can prove, preferably by making the probabilistic arguments rigorous, that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  3. One can prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable (say in Peano arithmetic or ZFC).



The goal here would be to find statements that are true 'just because they are probably true', not because we can put our finger on a reason why any individual one must be true.



An example of such a sequence of statements might be 'if $p_n$ is the $n$th prime, there are infinitely many repunit primes in base $p_n$'. However while this example meets condition 1 we seem far from having enough understanding of mathematics to prove 2, and 3 seems hopeless. I think we need a less charismatic sequence of statements that are more carefully crafted to the task at hand.










share|cite|improve this question















I'm wondering if anyone has found, or can find, a sequence of statements $P(n)$ ($n in mathbb{N}$) such that:




  1. Heuristic arguments using probability theory suggest that all the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  2. One can prove, preferably by making the probabilistic arguments rigorous, that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true.


  3. One can prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable (say in Peano arithmetic or ZFC).



The goal here would be to find statements that are true 'just because they are probably true', not because we can put our finger on a reason why any individual one must be true.



An example of such a sequence of statements might be 'if $p_n$ is the $n$th prime, there are infinitely many repunit primes in base $p_n$'. However while this example meets condition 1 we seem far from having enough understanding of mathematics to prove 2, and 3 seems hopeless. I think we need a less charismatic sequence of statements that are more carefully crafted to the task at hand.







nt.number-theory lo.logic






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Nov 16 at 22:52

























asked Nov 16 at 17:08









John Baez

8,4874593




8,4874593








  • 5




    It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
    – James Hanson
    Nov 16 at 17:19






  • 3




    What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
    – YCor
    Nov 16 at 18:13






  • 1




    Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
    – Ilya Bogdanov
    Nov 16 at 19:37








  • 1




    How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
    – Nik Weaver
    Nov 16 at 20:53






  • 3




    The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
    – John Baez
    Nov 16 at 22:11














  • 5




    It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
    – James Hanson
    Nov 16 at 17:19






  • 3




    What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
    – YCor
    Nov 16 at 18:13






  • 1




    Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
    – Ilya Bogdanov
    Nov 16 at 19:37








  • 1




    How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
    – Nik Weaver
    Nov 16 at 20:53






  • 3




    The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
    – John Baez
    Nov 16 at 22:11








5




5




It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
– James Hanson
Nov 16 at 17:19




It's not a fixed sequence but you can generate arbitrarily many probably true, ZFC independent statements by stating lower bounds on the Kolmogorov complexity of randomly generated binary strings. You can tune the probability that they're true by choosing the length of the string and the lower bound carefully.
– James Hanson
Nov 16 at 17:19




3




3




What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
– YCor
Nov 16 at 18:13




What's the difference between "true" and "provable"?
– YCor
Nov 16 at 18:13




1




1




Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
– Ilya Bogdanov
Nov 16 at 19:37






Do statements like the Paris-Hamilton theorem count?
– Ilya Bogdanov
Nov 16 at 19:37






1




1




How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
– Nik Weaver
Nov 16 at 20:53




How could you "prove that only finitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are provable" (condition 3) and also "prove that infinitely many of the statements $P(n)$ are true" (condition 2)? Is the latter proof supposed to depend on large cardinals or something?
– Nik Weaver
Nov 16 at 20:53




3




3




The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
– John Baez
Nov 16 at 22:11




The Parris-Harrington theorem gives an infinite sequence of statements $P(n)$ that are individually provable in Peano arithmetic, for which $forall n P(n)$ is not provable in PA. It also has nothing to do with probabilistic heuristics. So this fails to meet all three criteria I listed.
– John Baez
Nov 16 at 22:11










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
11
down vote













Let $c$ be a constant such that
$$mathrm{PA}notvdash K(x)ge c$$
for all binary strings $x$, where $K$ is Kolmogorov complexity. Such a $c$ exists by Chaitin's Incompleteness Theorem and the linked Q&A discusses how to find it in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$.



For any $d$, let $x_d$ be the indicator string for the primes among nonnegative integers $le d$. So for instance, $x_5=001101$ and $x_{9}=0011010100$.



Let $P_{d}(n)$ be the statement
$$K(x_{n+d})ge c.$$



Let $d$ be large and then let $P(n)=P_d(n)$ for all $n$.




  • If $d$ is large enough then heuristically all the $P(n)$ are true.*


  • By the Pigeonhole Principle in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$ we prove that all but finitely many $P(n)$ are true.


  • We cannot prove any particular $P(n)$ in $mathrm{PA}$.



(*) Heuristics may suggest something like $dge ccdot mathcal H(1/log c)$ where $mathcal H$ is the entropy function, and we heuristically assume the primes are "random modulo the Prime Number Theorem", but the primes are computable so that heuristic is not quite right (thanks @EmilJerabek).






share|cite|improve this answer



















  • 2




    But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
    – Emil Jeřábek
    Nov 16 at 22:11










  • @EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
    – Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
    Nov 16 at 22:16











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "504"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f315473%2fprobably-true-but-provably-unprovable%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
11
down vote













Let $c$ be a constant such that
$$mathrm{PA}notvdash K(x)ge c$$
for all binary strings $x$, where $K$ is Kolmogorov complexity. Such a $c$ exists by Chaitin's Incompleteness Theorem and the linked Q&A discusses how to find it in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$.



For any $d$, let $x_d$ be the indicator string for the primes among nonnegative integers $le d$. So for instance, $x_5=001101$ and $x_{9}=0011010100$.



Let $P_{d}(n)$ be the statement
$$K(x_{n+d})ge c.$$



Let $d$ be large and then let $P(n)=P_d(n)$ for all $n$.




  • If $d$ is large enough then heuristically all the $P(n)$ are true.*


  • By the Pigeonhole Principle in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$ we prove that all but finitely many $P(n)$ are true.


  • We cannot prove any particular $P(n)$ in $mathrm{PA}$.



(*) Heuristics may suggest something like $dge ccdot mathcal H(1/log c)$ where $mathcal H$ is the entropy function, and we heuristically assume the primes are "random modulo the Prime Number Theorem", but the primes are computable so that heuristic is not quite right (thanks @EmilJerabek).






share|cite|improve this answer



















  • 2




    But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
    – Emil Jeřábek
    Nov 16 at 22:11










  • @EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
    – Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
    Nov 16 at 22:16















up vote
11
down vote













Let $c$ be a constant such that
$$mathrm{PA}notvdash K(x)ge c$$
for all binary strings $x$, where $K$ is Kolmogorov complexity. Such a $c$ exists by Chaitin's Incompleteness Theorem and the linked Q&A discusses how to find it in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$.



For any $d$, let $x_d$ be the indicator string for the primes among nonnegative integers $le d$. So for instance, $x_5=001101$ and $x_{9}=0011010100$.



Let $P_{d}(n)$ be the statement
$$K(x_{n+d})ge c.$$



Let $d$ be large and then let $P(n)=P_d(n)$ for all $n$.




  • If $d$ is large enough then heuristically all the $P(n)$ are true.*


  • By the Pigeonhole Principle in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$ we prove that all but finitely many $P(n)$ are true.


  • We cannot prove any particular $P(n)$ in $mathrm{PA}$.



(*) Heuristics may suggest something like $dge ccdot mathcal H(1/log c)$ where $mathcal H$ is the entropy function, and we heuristically assume the primes are "random modulo the Prime Number Theorem", but the primes are computable so that heuristic is not quite right (thanks @EmilJerabek).






share|cite|improve this answer



















  • 2




    But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
    – Emil Jeřábek
    Nov 16 at 22:11










  • @EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
    – Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
    Nov 16 at 22:16













up vote
11
down vote










up vote
11
down vote









Let $c$ be a constant such that
$$mathrm{PA}notvdash K(x)ge c$$
for all binary strings $x$, where $K$ is Kolmogorov complexity. Such a $c$ exists by Chaitin's Incompleteness Theorem and the linked Q&A discusses how to find it in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$.



For any $d$, let $x_d$ be the indicator string for the primes among nonnegative integers $le d$. So for instance, $x_5=001101$ and $x_{9}=0011010100$.



Let $P_{d}(n)$ be the statement
$$K(x_{n+d})ge c.$$



Let $d$ be large and then let $P(n)=P_d(n)$ for all $n$.




  • If $d$ is large enough then heuristically all the $P(n)$ are true.*


  • By the Pigeonhole Principle in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$ we prove that all but finitely many $P(n)$ are true.


  • We cannot prove any particular $P(n)$ in $mathrm{PA}$.



(*) Heuristics may suggest something like $dge ccdot mathcal H(1/log c)$ where $mathcal H$ is the entropy function, and we heuristically assume the primes are "random modulo the Prime Number Theorem", but the primes are computable so that heuristic is not quite right (thanks @EmilJerabek).






share|cite|improve this answer














Let $c$ be a constant such that
$$mathrm{PA}notvdash K(x)ge c$$
for all binary strings $x$, where $K$ is Kolmogorov complexity. Such a $c$ exists by Chaitin's Incompleteness Theorem and the linked Q&A discusses how to find it in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$.



For any $d$, let $x_d$ be the indicator string for the primes among nonnegative integers $le d$. So for instance, $x_5=001101$ and $x_{9}=0011010100$.



Let $P_{d}(n)$ be the statement
$$K(x_{n+d})ge c.$$



Let $d$ be large and then let $P(n)=P_d(n)$ for all $n$.




  • If $d$ is large enough then heuristically all the $P(n)$ are true.*


  • By the Pigeonhole Principle in $mathrm{PA}+mathrm{Con}(mathrm{PA})$ we prove that all but finitely many $P(n)$ are true.


  • We cannot prove any particular $P(n)$ in $mathrm{PA}$.



(*) Heuristics may suggest something like $dge ccdot mathcal H(1/log c)$ where $mathcal H$ is the entropy function, and we heuristically assume the primes are "random modulo the Prime Number Theorem", but the primes are computable so that heuristic is not quite right (thanks @EmilJerabek).







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Nov 16 at 22:15

























answered Nov 16 at 21:43









Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen

17.6k33786




17.6k33786








  • 2




    But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
    – Emil Jeřábek
    Nov 16 at 22:11










  • @EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
    – Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
    Nov 16 at 22:16














  • 2




    But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
    – Emil Jeřábek
    Nov 16 at 22:11










  • @EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
    – Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
    Nov 16 at 22:16








2




2




But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
– Emil Jeřábek
Nov 16 at 22:11




But primes are not random at all, they are computable. Thus the Kolmogorov complexity of $x_d$ is a constant plus the Kolmogorov complexity of $d$. If you defined $x_d$ as a string of $d$ zeros, it would behave in an essentially identical way.
– Emil Jeřábek
Nov 16 at 22:11












@EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
– Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
Nov 16 at 22:16




@EmilJeřábek right, I'll update...
– Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen
Nov 16 at 22:16


















 

draft saved


draft discarded



















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f315473%2fprobably-true-but-provably-unprovable%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Probability when a professor distributes a quiz and homework assignment to a class of n students.

Aardman Animations

Are they similar matrix