Terence Tao Exercise 5.4.3: Integer part of $x$ proof.
$begingroup$
I am reading Terence Tao: Analysis 1.
As you may be aware, certain objects are introduced bit by bit, so if i am not 'allowed' to use something yet, please understand.
Show that for every real number $x$ there is exactly one integer $N$ such that
$ N leq x < N + 1$
If $x = 0$ then we can take $N = 0$.
If $x > 0$ then $x$ is the formal limit of some Cauchy sequence $(a_n)$, of which is positively bounded away from zero. Since $(a_n)$ is Cauchy it is bounded by some rational $M$, this implies that $x leq M$, if we take $M < N + 1$ for some integer $N$ then $x < N + 1$.
I seem to think this part is fine, but thinking is dangerous.
I now need to show that $ N leq x $.
I know that the sequence $(a_n)$ is bounded away from zero, so every term of the sequence $a_n > c$ for some rational $c$ But i don't think this gets me any further.
Surely i could use this as i know x is the formal limit of the sequence of rationals $(a_n)$ but i cant quite make the connection.
EDIT:
I know i have to prove that this is true when x < 0, but i have not completed from x > 0.
I know i can use Cauchy sequences, division algorithm... its pretty hard for me to say what i can't use because I am an undergraduate. I'm sorry if that makes it impossible to answer for some, it's very awkward i must admit. What i can tell you is the next chapter is on the least upper bound property.
analysis
$endgroup$
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
I am reading Terence Tao: Analysis 1.
As you may be aware, certain objects are introduced bit by bit, so if i am not 'allowed' to use something yet, please understand.
Show that for every real number $x$ there is exactly one integer $N$ such that
$ N leq x < N + 1$
If $x = 0$ then we can take $N = 0$.
If $x > 0$ then $x$ is the formal limit of some Cauchy sequence $(a_n)$, of which is positively bounded away from zero. Since $(a_n)$ is Cauchy it is bounded by some rational $M$, this implies that $x leq M$, if we take $M < N + 1$ for some integer $N$ then $x < N + 1$.
I seem to think this part is fine, but thinking is dangerous.
I now need to show that $ N leq x $.
I know that the sequence $(a_n)$ is bounded away from zero, so every term of the sequence $a_n > c$ for some rational $c$ But i don't think this gets me any further.
Surely i could use this as i know x is the formal limit of the sequence of rationals $(a_n)$ but i cant quite make the connection.
EDIT:
I know i have to prove that this is true when x < 0, but i have not completed from x > 0.
I know i can use Cauchy sequences, division algorithm... its pretty hard for me to say what i can't use because I am an undergraduate. I'm sorry if that makes it impossible to answer for some, it's very awkward i must admit. What i can tell you is the next chapter is on the least upper bound property.
analysis
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
2
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
I am reading Terence Tao: Analysis 1.
As you may be aware, certain objects are introduced bit by bit, so if i am not 'allowed' to use something yet, please understand.
Show that for every real number $x$ there is exactly one integer $N$ such that
$ N leq x < N + 1$
If $x = 0$ then we can take $N = 0$.
If $x > 0$ then $x$ is the formal limit of some Cauchy sequence $(a_n)$, of which is positively bounded away from zero. Since $(a_n)$ is Cauchy it is bounded by some rational $M$, this implies that $x leq M$, if we take $M < N + 1$ for some integer $N$ then $x < N + 1$.
I seem to think this part is fine, but thinking is dangerous.
I now need to show that $ N leq x $.
I know that the sequence $(a_n)$ is bounded away from zero, so every term of the sequence $a_n > c$ for some rational $c$ But i don't think this gets me any further.
Surely i could use this as i know x is the formal limit of the sequence of rationals $(a_n)$ but i cant quite make the connection.
EDIT:
I know i have to prove that this is true when x < 0, but i have not completed from x > 0.
I know i can use Cauchy sequences, division algorithm... its pretty hard for me to say what i can't use because I am an undergraduate. I'm sorry if that makes it impossible to answer for some, it's very awkward i must admit. What i can tell you is the next chapter is on the least upper bound property.
analysis
$endgroup$
I am reading Terence Tao: Analysis 1.
As you may be aware, certain objects are introduced bit by bit, so if i am not 'allowed' to use something yet, please understand.
Show that for every real number $x$ there is exactly one integer $N$ such that
$ N leq x < N + 1$
If $x = 0$ then we can take $N = 0$.
If $x > 0$ then $x$ is the formal limit of some Cauchy sequence $(a_n)$, of which is positively bounded away from zero. Since $(a_n)$ is Cauchy it is bounded by some rational $M$, this implies that $x leq M$, if we take $M < N + 1$ for some integer $N$ then $x < N + 1$.
I seem to think this part is fine, but thinking is dangerous.
I now need to show that $ N leq x $.
I know that the sequence $(a_n)$ is bounded away from zero, so every term of the sequence $a_n > c$ for some rational $c$ But i don't think this gets me any further.
Surely i could use this as i know x is the formal limit of the sequence of rationals $(a_n)$ but i cant quite make the connection.
EDIT:
I know i have to prove that this is true when x < 0, but i have not completed from x > 0.
I know i can use Cauchy sequences, division algorithm... its pretty hard for me to say what i can't use because I am an undergraduate. I'm sorry if that makes it impossible to answer for some, it's very awkward i must admit. What i can tell you is the next chapter is on the least upper bound property.
analysis
analysis
edited Feb 9 '15 at 14:45
asked Feb 9 '15 at 14:32
user214138
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
2
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43
|
show 3 more comments
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
2
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
2
2
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43
|
show 3 more comments
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Let $x=(x_1,x_2,dots,x_n,dots)$ be a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, and let $epsilon=frac{1}{2}$. Then there exists an $M$ such that if $n,mgeq M$, $|x_n-x_m|<epsilon$. That means, in particular, $xin [x_M-frac{1}{2},x_M+frac{1}{2}]$.
Use the theorem for rational numbers, to show that there is an integer part $N_0$ of $x_M-frac{1}{2}$, and that $N_0leq x<N_0+2$. Then either $N_0leq x<N_0+1$ or $N_0+1leq x<N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $x>0$ consider the set of natural numbers that are larger than $x$. It is non-empty by the Archimedean property, and it has a first element. Call that element $N+1$. We must have $Nleq x$ because otherwise $N+1$ wouldn't be the first element.
Your approach it leaving the chosen $N$ too lose because you are choosing it to be any $M<N+1$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The idea is that if your sequence does not limit to an integer, then eventually all of the terms in the sequence must have the same integer part. Let's see if we can formalize this.
Let $d = inf{|N-x| : Nin mathbb{Z}}$. This is a nonempty set of
reals so it has an infimum. If $d = 0$, then $xinmathbb{Z}$ and
you're done.
On reread, the above paragraph is suspect but I have to run and won't be able to fix it properly until later. Also if the next chapter is on the least upper bound property, you may not yet know that all sets of real numbers have infima and suprema.
Now write $x = lim_m a_m$ where $a_m$ is a Cauchy sequence of rationals. Let $M$ be such that $m>M$ implies $|a_m - x|<d$. Observe (why?) that each $a_m$ may be written uniquely as $A_m + r_m$ where $A_minmathbb{Z}$ and $r_min [0,1)$.
Now can you prove that $A_m = A_n$ for all $m,n>M$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Given the sequence $(x_i)=x$ consider the sequences $(lfloor x_irfloor)=lfloor x rfloor $and $(lceil x_irceil)=lceil xrceil$. Where $lfloor x_irfloor$ is the gratest integer $<x_i$ and $lceil x_irceil$ is the lowest integer $>x_i$.
You can proof that if $(x_i)$ is Cauchy, than $lfloor x rfloor$ and $lceil xrceil$ are Cauchy sequences that define successive integers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since x is a real number it is the limit of some Cauchy sequence. Then this sequence is bounded by some M, where M is rational, so by the same propositon for rationals from Tao's book, we have that there exists an integer N such that N is less than or equal to M, and M is less than N + 1.
Since N is less than or equal to M we now that there exists some rational number which is the member of the sequence such that it is greater or equal to N and less than or equal to M.
Thus we have that N is less than or equal to x and x is less than N + 1, as desired.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
First show that such an N exists, then show that it is unique.
$x$ can be exactly one of zero, positive or negative (Prop. 5.4.4).
For the easiest case, if $x=0$, we have $N = 0$.
Let x be positive. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such an N does not exist. With this assumption we can prove by induction that $k leq x$ for any integer $kgeq 0$. Use $k=0$ as the base case. $0 leq x$ is true, as $x$ is positive. Assume that $kleq x$ for some $kgeq 0$, then consider $k+1 leq x$. By our assumption that $N$ does not exist, $k+1leq x$ must be true. This closes the induction.
But we know the conclusion is false. There must exist an integer $M$ such that $Mgt x$, as reals are bounded by a rational (Prop. 5.4.12), and integers are interspersed by rationals (Prop. 4.4.1). We can therefore conclude that such an $N$ exists.
- A similar induction can be constructed when x is negative.*
Now show that $N$ is unique. Let there be two integers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that both $n_1 leq x lt n_1 + 1$ and $n_2 leq x lt n_2 + 1$. Let $n_1$ < $n_2$ (one must be less than the other since they cannot be equal).
$$
begin{align}
&n_1 le n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq x && text{as $n_2 leq x$} \
&implies text{false} &&text{as we assumed $n_1 + 1 > x$}
end{align}
$$
Thus, there exists a unique integer $N$ such that $N leq x lt N + 1$.
* Instead of breaking this proof into cases $x=0$, $x>0$ and $x<0$, you may wish to first prove that reals are bounded below by integers, a relatively simple extension of Prop. 5.4.12, then you may choose such an integer for the base case of the induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1140683%2fterence-tao-exercise-5-4-3-integer-part-of-x-proof%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Let $x=(x_1,x_2,dots,x_n,dots)$ be a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, and let $epsilon=frac{1}{2}$. Then there exists an $M$ such that if $n,mgeq M$, $|x_n-x_m|<epsilon$. That means, in particular, $xin [x_M-frac{1}{2},x_M+frac{1}{2}]$.
Use the theorem for rational numbers, to show that there is an integer part $N_0$ of $x_M-frac{1}{2}$, and that $N_0leq x<N_0+2$. Then either $N_0leq x<N_0+1$ or $N_0+1leq x<N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $x=(x_1,x_2,dots,x_n,dots)$ be a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, and let $epsilon=frac{1}{2}$. Then there exists an $M$ such that if $n,mgeq M$, $|x_n-x_m|<epsilon$. That means, in particular, $xin [x_M-frac{1}{2},x_M+frac{1}{2}]$.
Use the theorem for rational numbers, to show that there is an integer part $N_0$ of $x_M-frac{1}{2}$, and that $N_0leq x<N_0+2$. Then either $N_0leq x<N_0+1$ or $N_0+1leq x<N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $x=(x_1,x_2,dots,x_n,dots)$ be a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, and let $epsilon=frac{1}{2}$. Then there exists an $M$ such that if $n,mgeq M$, $|x_n-x_m|<epsilon$. That means, in particular, $xin [x_M-frac{1}{2},x_M+frac{1}{2}]$.
Use the theorem for rational numbers, to show that there is an integer part $N_0$ of $x_M-frac{1}{2}$, and that $N_0leq x<N_0+2$. Then either $N_0leq x<N_0+1$ or $N_0+1leq x<N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
Let $x=(x_1,x_2,dots,x_n,dots)$ be a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, and let $epsilon=frac{1}{2}$. Then there exists an $M$ such that if $n,mgeq M$, $|x_n-x_m|<epsilon$. That means, in particular, $xin [x_M-frac{1}{2},x_M+frac{1}{2}]$.
Use the theorem for rational numbers, to show that there is an integer part $N_0$ of $x_M-frac{1}{2}$, and that $N_0leq x<N_0+2$. Then either $N_0leq x<N_0+1$ or $N_0+1leq x<N_0+2$.
answered Feb 9 '15 at 14:51
Thomas AndrewsThomas Andrews
130k12147298
130k12147298
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
add a comment |
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
By 'theorem for rational numbers' your referring to the exercise that proved the theorem in the book that i mentioned in the comments? i.e $ n leq x < n + 1$ where x is ratonal
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:57
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Yes, so use that theorem to find $N_0$ so that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. Then show that $N_0leq xleq N_0+2$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:59
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
$begingroup$
Is that last part of the last comment a typo?
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:01
1
1
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
$begingroup$
No, it is $2$. You only know that $N_0leq x_M-frac{1}{2}<N_0+1$. But we only know that $x_M-frac{1}{2}leq xleq x_M+frac{1}{2}$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 15:02
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $x>0$ consider the set of natural numbers that are larger than $x$. It is non-empty by the Archimedean property, and it has a first element. Call that element $N+1$. We must have $Nleq x$ because otherwise $N+1$ wouldn't be the first element.
Your approach it leaving the chosen $N$ too lose because you are choosing it to be any $M<N+1$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $x>0$ consider the set of natural numbers that are larger than $x$. It is non-empty by the Archimedean property, and it has a first element. Call that element $N+1$. We must have $Nleq x$ because otherwise $N+1$ wouldn't be the first element.
Your approach it leaving the chosen $N$ too lose because you are choosing it to be any $M<N+1$.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $x>0$ consider the set of natural numbers that are larger than $x$. It is non-empty by the Archimedean property, and it has a first element. Call that element $N+1$. We must have $Nleq x$ because otherwise $N+1$ wouldn't be the first element.
Your approach it leaving the chosen $N$ too lose because you are choosing it to be any $M<N+1$.
$endgroup$
If $x>0$ consider the set of natural numbers that are larger than $x$. It is non-empty by the Archimedean property, and it has a first element. Call that element $N+1$. We must have $Nleq x$ because otherwise $N+1$ wouldn't be the first element.
Your approach it leaving the chosen $N$ too lose because you are choosing it to be any $M<N+1$.
answered Feb 9 '15 at 14:37
CarolCarol
41827
41827
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The idea is that if your sequence does not limit to an integer, then eventually all of the terms in the sequence must have the same integer part. Let's see if we can formalize this.
Let $d = inf{|N-x| : Nin mathbb{Z}}$. This is a nonempty set of
reals so it has an infimum. If $d = 0$, then $xinmathbb{Z}$ and
you're done.
On reread, the above paragraph is suspect but I have to run and won't be able to fix it properly until later. Also if the next chapter is on the least upper bound property, you may not yet know that all sets of real numbers have infima and suprema.
Now write $x = lim_m a_m$ where $a_m$ is a Cauchy sequence of rationals. Let $M$ be such that $m>M$ implies $|a_m - x|<d$. Observe (why?) that each $a_m$ may be written uniquely as $A_m + r_m$ where $A_minmathbb{Z}$ and $r_min [0,1)$.
Now can you prove that $A_m = A_n$ for all $m,n>M$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The idea is that if your sequence does not limit to an integer, then eventually all of the terms in the sequence must have the same integer part. Let's see if we can formalize this.
Let $d = inf{|N-x| : Nin mathbb{Z}}$. This is a nonempty set of
reals so it has an infimum. If $d = 0$, then $xinmathbb{Z}$ and
you're done.
On reread, the above paragraph is suspect but I have to run and won't be able to fix it properly until later. Also if the next chapter is on the least upper bound property, you may not yet know that all sets of real numbers have infima and suprema.
Now write $x = lim_m a_m$ where $a_m$ is a Cauchy sequence of rationals. Let $M$ be such that $m>M$ implies $|a_m - x|<d$. Observe (why?) that each $a_m$ may be written uniquely as $A_m + r_m$ where $A_minmathbb{Z}$ and $r_min [0,1)$.
Now can you prove that $A_m = A_n$ for all $m,n>M$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The idea is that if your sequence does not limit to an integer, then eventually all of the terms in the sequence must have the same integer part. Let's see if we can formalize this.
Let $d = inf{|N-x| : Nin mathbb{Z}}$. This is a nonempty set of
reals so it has an infimum. If $d = 0$, then $xinmathbb{Z}$ and
you're done.
On reread, the above paragraph is suspect but I have to run and won't be able to fix it properly until later. Also if the next chapter is on the least upper bound property, you may not yet know that all sets of real numbers have infima and suprema.
Now write $x = lim_m a_m$ where $a_m$ is a Cauchy sequence of rationals. Let $M$ be such that $m>M$ implies $|a_m - x|<d$. Observe (why?) that each $a_m$ may be written uniquely as $A_m + r_m$ where $A_minmathbb{Z}$ and $r_min [0,1)$.
Now can you prove that $A_m = A_n$ for all $m,n>M$?
$endgroup$
The idea is that if your sequence does not limit to an integer, then eventually all of the terms in the sequence must have the same integer part. Let's see if we can formalize this.
Let $d = inf{|N-x| : Nin mathbb{Z}}$. This is a nonempty set of
reals so it has an infimum. If $d = 0$, then $xinmathbb{Z}$ and
you're done.
On reread, the above paragraph is suspect but I have to run and won't be able to fix it properly until later. Also if the next chapter is on the least upper bound property, you may not yet know that all sets of real numbers have infima and suprema.
Now write $x = lim_m a_m$ where $a_m$ is a Cauchy sequence of rationals. Let $M$ be such that $m>M$ implies $|a_m - x|<d$. Observe (why?) that each $a_m$ may be written uniquely as $A_m + r_m$ where $A_minmathbb{Z}$ and $r_min [0,1)$.
Now can you prove that $A_m = A_n$ for all $m,n>M$?
answered Feb 9 '15 at 14:51
NealNeal
24k24087
24k24087
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
$begingroup$
I am really sorry for wasting your time Neal, the next chapter is on supremum(least upper bound) and infimum.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 15:04
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Given the sequence $(x_i)=x$ consider the sequences $(lfloor x_irfloor)=lfloor x rfloor $and $(lceil x_irceil)=lceil xrceil$. Where $lfloor x_irfloor$ is the gratest integer $<x_i$ and $lceil x_irceil$ is the lowest integer $>x_i$.
You can proof that if $(x_i)$ is Cauchy, than $lfloor x rfloor$ and $lceil xrceil$ are Cauchy sequences that define successive integers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Given the sequence $(x_i)=x$ consider the sequences $(lfloor x_irfloor)=lfloor x rfloor $and $(lceil x_irceil)=lceil xrceil$. Where $lfloor x_irfloor$ is the gratest integer $<x_i$ and $lceil x_irceil$ is the lowest integer $>x_i$.
You can proof that if $(x_i)$ is Cauchy, than $lfloor x rfloor$ and $lceil xrceil$ are Cauchy sequences that define successive integers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Given the sequence $(x_i)=x$ consider the sequences $(lfloor x_irfloor)=lfloor x rfloor $and $(lceil x_irceil)=lceil xrceil$. Where $lfloor x_irfloor$ is the gratest integer $<x_i$ and $lceil x_irceil$ is the lowest integer $>x_i$.
You can proof that if $(x_i)$ is Cauchy, than $lfloor x rfloor$ and $lceil xrceil$ are Cauchy sequences that define successive integers.
$endgroup$
Given the sequence $(x_i)=x$ consider the sequences $(lfloor x_irfloor)=lfloor x rfloor $and $(lceil x_irceil)=lceil xrceil$. Where $lfloor x_irfloor$ is the gratest integer $<x_i$ and $lceil x_irceil$ is the lowest integer $>x_i$.
You can proof that if $(x_i)$ is Cauchy, than $lfloor x rfloor$ and $lceil xrceil$ are Cauchy sequences that define successive integers.
answered Feb 9 '15 at 15:18
Emilio NovatiEmilio Novati
52.2k43474
52.2k43474
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since x is a real number it is the limit of some Cauchy sequence. Then this sequence is bounded by some M, where M is rational, so by the same propositon for rationals from Tao's book, we have that there exists an integer N such that N is less than or equal to M, and M is less than N + 1.
Since N is less than or equal to M we now that there exists some rational number which is the member of the sequence such that it is greater or equal to N and less than or equal to M.
Thus we have that N is less than or equal to x and x is less than N + 1, as desired.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since x is a real number it is the limit of some Cauchy sequence. Then this sequence is bounded by some M, where M is rational, so by the same propositon for rationals from Tao's book, we have that there exists an integer N such that N is less than or equal to M, and M is less than N + 1.
Since N is less than or equal to M we now that there exists some rational number which is the member of the sequence such that it is greater or equal to N and less than or equal to M.
Thus we have that N is less than or equal to x and x is less than N + 1, as desired.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since x is a real number it is the limit of some Cauchy sequence. Then this sequence is bounded by some M, where M is rational, so by the same propositon for rationals from Tao's book, we have that there exists an integer N such that N is less than or equal to M, and M is less than N + 1.
Since N is less than or equal to M we now that there exists some rational number which is the member of the sequence such that it is greater or equal to N and less than or equal to M.
Thus we have that N is less than or equal to x and x is less than N + 1, as desired.
$endgroup$
Since x is a real number it is the limit of some Cauchy sequence. Then this sequence is bounded by some M, where M is rational, so by the same propositon for rationals from Tao's book, we have that there exists an integer N such that N is less than or equal to M, and M is less than N + 1.
Since N is less than or equal to M we now that there exists some rational number which is the member of the sequence such that it is greater or equal to N and less than or equal to M.
Thus we have that N is less than or equal to x and x is less than N + 1, as desired.
answered Apr 13 '16 at 18:44
KoleKole
1
1
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
First show that such an N exists, then show that it is unique.
$x$ can be exactly one of zero, positive or negative (Prop. 5.4.4).
For the easiest case, if $x=0$, we have $N = 0$.
Let x be positive. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such an N does not exist. With this assumption we can prove by induction that $k leq x$ for any integer $kgeq 0$. Use $k=0$ as the base case. $0 leq x$ is true, as $x$ is positive. Assume that $kleq x$ for some $kgeq 0$, then consider $k+1 leq x$. By our assumption that $N$ does not exist, $k+1leq x$ must be true. This closes the induction.
But we know the conclusion is false. There must exist an integer $M$ such that $Mgt x$, as reals are bounded by a rational (Prop. 5.4.12), and integers are interspersed by rationals (Prop. 4.4.1). We can therefore conclude that such an $N$ exists.
- A similar induction can be constructed when x is negative.*
Now show that $N$ is unique. Let there be two integers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that both $n_1 leq x lt n_1 + 1$ and $n_2 leq x lt n_2 + 1$. Let $n_1$ < $n_2$ (one must be less than the other since they cannot be equal).
$$
begin{align}
&n_1 le n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq x && text{as $n_2 leq x$} \
&implies text{false} &&text{as we assumed $n_1 + 1 > x$}
end{align}
$$
Thus, there exists a unique integer $N$ such that $N leq x lt N + 1$.
* Instead of breaking this proof into cases $x=0$, $x>0$ and $x<0$, you may wish to first prove that reals are bounded below by integers, a relatively simple extension of Prop. 5.4.12, then you may choose such an integer for the base case of the induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
First show that such an N exists, then show that it is unique.
$x$ can be exactly one of zero, positive or negative (Prop. 5.4.4).
For the easiest case, if $x=0$, we have $N = 0$.
Let x be positive. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such an N does not exist. With this assumption we can prove by induction that $k leq x$ for any integer $kgeq 0$. Use $k=0$ as the base case. $0 leq x$ is true, as $x$ is positive. Assume that $kleq x$ for some $kgeq 0$, then consider $k+1 leq x$. By our assumption that $N$ does not exist, $k+1leq x$ must be true. This closes the induction.
But we know the conclusion is false. There must exist an integer $M$ such that $Mgt x$, as reals are bounded by a rational (Prop. 5.4.12), and integers are interspersed by rationals (Prop. 4.4.1). We can therefore conclude that such an $N$ exists.
- A similar induction can be constructed when x is negative.*
Now show that $N$ is unique. Let there be two integers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that both $n_1 leq x lt n_1 + 1$ and $n_2 leq x lt n_2 + 1$. Let $n_1$ < $n_2$ (one must be less than the other since they cannot be equal).
$$
begin{align}
&n_1 le n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq x && text{as $n_2 leq x$} \
&implies text{false} &&text{as we assumed $n_1 + 1 > x$}
end{align}
$$
Thus, there exists a unique integer $N$ such that $N leq x lt N + 1$.
* Instead of breaking this proof into cases $x=0$, $x>0$ and $x<0$, you may wish to first prove that reals are bounded below by integers, a relatively simple extension of Prop. 5.4.12, then you may choose such an integer for the base case of the induction.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
First show that such an N exists, then show that it is unique.
$x$ can be exactly one of zero, positive or negative (Prop. 5.4.4).
For the easiest case, if $x=0$, we have $N = 0$.
Let x be positive. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such an N does not exist. With this assumption we can prove by induction that $k leq x$ for any integer $kgeq 0$. Use $k=0$ as the base case. $0 leq x$ is true, as $x$ is positive. Assume that $kleq x$ for some $kgeq 0$, then consider $k+1 leq x$. By our assumption that $N$ does not exist, $k+1leq x$ must be true. This closes the induction.
But we know the conclusion is false. There must exist an integer $M$ such that $Mgt x$, as reals are bounded by a rational (Prop. 5.4.12), and integers are interspersed by rationals (Prop. 4.4.1). We can therefore conclude that such an $N$ exists.
- A similar induction can be constructed when x is negative.*
Now show that $N$ is unique. Let there be two integers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that both $n_1 leq x lt n_1 + 1$ and $n_2 leq x lt n_2 + 1$. Let $n_1$ < $n_2$ (one must be less than the other since they cannot be equal).
$$
begin{align}
&n_1 le n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq x && text{as $n_2 leq x$} \
&implies text{false} &&text{as we assumed $n_1 + 1 > x$}
end{align}
$$
Thus, there exists a unique integer $N$ such that $N leq x lt N + 1$.
* Instead of breaking this proof into cases $x=0$, $x>0$ and $x<0$, you may wish to first prove that reals are bounded below by integers, a relatively simple extension of Prop. 5.4.12, then you may choose such an integer for the base case of the induction.
$endgroup$
First show that such an N exists, then show that it is unique.
$x$ can be exactly one of zero, positive or negative (Prop. 5.4.4).
For the easiest case, if $x=0$, we have $N = 0$.
Let x be positive. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that such an N does not exist. With this assumption we can prove by induction that $k leq x$ for any integer $kgeq 0$. Use $k=0$ as the base case. $0 leq x$ is true, as $x$ is positive. Assume that $kleq x$ for some $kgeq 0$, then consider $k+1 leq x$. By our assumption that $N$ does not exist, $k+1leq x$ must be true. This closes the induction.
But we know the conclusion is false. There must exist an integer $M$ such that $Mgt x$, as reals are bounded by a rational (Prop. 5.4.12), and integers are interspersed by rationals (Prop. 4.4.1). We can therefore conclude that such an $N$ exists.
- A similar induction can be constructed when x is negative.*
Now show that $N$ is unique. Let there be two integers $n_1$ and $n_2$ such that both $n_1 leq x lt n_1 + 1$ and $n_2 leq x lt n_2 + 1$. Let $n_1$ < $n_2$ (one must be less than the other since they cannot be equal).
$$
begin{align}
&n_1 le n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq n_2 \
&implies n_1 + 1 leq x && text{as $n_2 leq x$} \
&implies text{false} &&text{as we assumed $n_1 + 1 > x$}
end{align}
$$
Thus, there exists a unique integer $N$ such that $N leq x lt N + 1$.
* Instead of breaking this proof into cases $x=0$, $x>0$ and $x<0$, you may wish to first prove that reals are bounded below by integers, a relatively simple extension of Prop. 5.4.12, then you may choose such an integer for the base case of the induction.
answered Dec 28 '18 at 1:44
KevinKevin
1012
1012
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1140683%2fterence-tao-exercise-5-4-3-integer-part-of-x-proof%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
Hmm. Is this really how Tao introduces the integer part? Seems unnecessarily complicated.
$endgroup$
– Tim Raczkowski
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
It's something thatneeds to be proven, @TimRaczkowski.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:39
$begingroup$
There is one Exercise earlier on in the book, in which x is rational, thats nice and easy, but this one is a little tricky for me.
$endgroup$
– user214138
Feb 9 '15 at 14:40
$begingroup$
Using Cauchy sequences is trick for this sort of problem, because the integer part of each of $0.9,0.99,cdots,0.99dots9,cdots$ is $0$, but the integer part of the limit is $1$.
$endgroup$
– Thomas Andrews
Feb 9 '15 at 14:41
2
$begingroup$
Would you mind editing into the question which facts you're allowed to use and which facts you're not?
$endgroup$
– Neal
Feb 9 '15 at 14:43