Why are model theorists so fond of definable groups?












15












$begingroup$


My PhD was on so called "pure" model theory, and my advisor was not very much interested in applications of model theory to algebra. Now I feel the need to fill in the gap, and I'd like to educate myself on applied model theory.
One of the questions I always asked myself is about the study of groups definable (or interpretable) in some structures : it seems that model theorists are very fond of that, since a long time ago (at least since the 70's to my knowledge, and even quite recently with works about groups definable in NIP structures by Pillay).
Why is it so ?
I guess that the origin of all this is the fact that groups definable in ACF are precisely algebraic groups. This is indeed a nice link between model theory and algebraic geometry (by the way, does this link has brought something interesting and new to algebraic geometry, or has it always been just a slightly different point of view ?). But if it is so, why going on to study extensively groups definable on such exotic kind of theories as NIP or simple for example ? Is it only because something can be said about those groups and that groups are prestigious objects within mathematics, or are there deeper reasons ?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 14:57






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 15:36






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
    $endgroup$
    – YCor
    Feb 10 at 17:03






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 17:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
    $endgroup$
    – Matt F.
    Feb 10 at 18:07
















15












$begingroup$


My PhD was on so called "pure" model theory, and my advisor was not very much interested in applications of model theory to algebra. Now I feel the need to fill in the gap, and I'd like to educate myself on applied model theory.
One of the questions I always asked myself is about the study of groups definable (or interpretable) in some structures : it seems that model theorists are very fond of that, since a long time ago (at least since the 70's to my knowledge, and even quite recently with works about groups definable in NIP structures by Pillay).
Why is it so ?
I guess that the origin of all this is the fact that groups definable in ACF are precisely algebraic groups. This is indeed a nice link between model theory and algebraic geometry (by the way, does this link has brought something interesting and new to algebraic geometry, or has it always been just a slightly different point of view ?). But if it is so, why going on to study extensively groups definable on such exotic kind of theories as NIP or simple for example ? Is it only because something can be said about those groups and that groups are prestigious objects within mathematics, or are there deeper reasons ?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 14:57






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 15:36






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
    $endgroup$
    – YCor
    Feb 10 at 17:03






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 17:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
    $endgroup$
    – Matt F.
    Feb 10 at 18:07














15












15








15


2



$begingroup$


My PhD was on so called "pure" model theory, and my advisor was not very much interested in applications of model theory to algebra. Now I feel the need to fill in the gap, and I'd like to educate myself on applied model theory.
One of the questions I always asked myself is about the study of groups definable (or interpretable) in some structures : it seems that model theorists are very fond of that, since a long time ago (at least since the 70's to my knowledge, and even quite recently with works about groups definable in NIP structures by Pillay).
Why is it so ?
I guess that the origin of all this is the fact that groups definable in ACF are precisely algebraic groups. This is indeed a nice link between model theory and algebraic geometry (by the way, does this link has brought something interesting and new to algebraic geometry, or has it always been just a slightly different point of view ?). But if it is so, why going on to study extensively groups definable on such exotic kind of theories as NIP or simple for example ? Is it only because something can be said about those groups and that groups are prestigious objects within mathematics, or are there deeper reasons ?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




My PhD was on so called "pure" model theory, and my advisor was not very much interested in applications of model theory to algebra. Now I feel the need to fill in the gap, and I'd like to educate myself on applied model theory.
One of the questions I always asked myself is about the study of groups definable (or interpretable) in some structures : it seems that model theorists are very fond of that, since a long time ago (at least since the 70's to my knowledge, and even quite recently with works about groups definable in NIP structures by Pillay).
Why is it so ?
I guess that the origin of all this is the fact that groups definable in ACF are precisely algebraic groups. This is indeed a nice link between model theory and algebraic geometry (by the way, does this link has brought something interesting and new to algebraic geometry, or has it always been just a slightly different point of view ?). But if it is so, why going on to study extensively groups definable on such exotic kind of theories as NIP or simple for example ? Is it only because something can be said about those groups and that groups are prestigious objects within mathematics, or are there deeper reasons ?







gr.group-theory lo.logic model-theory






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Feb 10 at 16:35







huurd

















asked Feb 10 at 13:22









huurdhuurd

994




994








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 14:57






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 15:36






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
    $endgroup$
    – YCor
    Feb 10 at 17:03






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 17:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
    $endgroup$
    – Matt F.
    Feb 10 at 18:07














  • 2




    $begingroup$
    I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 14:57






  • 7




    $begingroup$
    Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
    $endgroup$
    – Max
    Feb 10 at 15:36






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
    $endgroup$
    – YCor
    Feb 10 at 17:03






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 17:50








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
    $endgroup$
    – Matt F.
    Feb 10 at 18:07








2




2




$begingroup$
I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
$endgroup$
– Max
Feb 10 at 14:57




$begingroup$
I'm definitely not an expert; but isn't it simply because model theory is about definable things, and so the only groups that sit inside structures that you can talk about are the definable/interpretable ones ?
$endgroup$
– Max
Feb 10 at 14:57




7




7




$begingroup$
Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
$endgroup$
– Max
Feb 10 at 15:36




$begingroup$
Oh you were asking about why "definable groups", I thought you were asking about why "definable groups"; my bad
$endgroup$
– Max
Feb 10 at 15:36




3




3




$begingroup$
I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
$endgroup$
– YCor
Feb 10 at 17:03




$begingroup$
I think that groups being prestigious is a significant reason (which of course is related to good reasons to being prestigious). And also it is easier to continue in a well-studied topic (model theory of groups) than opening a new topic.
$endgroup$
– YCor
Feb 10 at 17:03




1




1




$begingroup$
@MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 17:50






$begingroup$
@MattF. The claim that every topological $4$-manifold is homeomorphic to a semi-algebraic set seems unlikely to me, but I don't know enough topology to assess it. Even if it's true, the category of topological $4$-manifolds definitely won't be equivalent to the semi-algebraic category - there just aren't enough semi-algebraically definable functions. But all that aside, I'm not sure what your point is here. How is this discussion relevant to the question?
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 17:50






1




1




$begingroup$
@IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
$endgroup$
– Matt F.
Feb 10 at 18:07




$begingroup$
@IvanDiLiberti, apparently not all topological 4-manifolds are triangulable (en.wikipedia.org/wiki/E8_manifold#History), so I will need to see how if there is a better formulation for the topological category. Up until just now, I knew about the failure of unique triangulation, but I will need to think more about this lack of triangulability.
$endgroup$
– Matt F.
Feb 10 at 18:07










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















11












$begingroup$

Here are a few reasons. These are just my perspectives - some people may disagree, and I'm sure there are good reasons to study definable groups that I'm missing.




  1. Mathematicians in general are fond of groups. There is a general theme in mathematics (with different motivations in different contexts) of developing a theory of group objects in any category of interest. For example, algebraic groups are group objects in the category of algebraic varieties, Lie groups are group objects in the category of differentiable manifolds, topological groups are group objects in the category of topological spaces, etc. Model theorists study the category of definable sets relative to a first-order theory, and group objects in this category are definable groups. [Aside: I'm confused by your comment "model theory is not mainly about definable things in my opinion". If it's not about definable things, what is it about?] Moreover, it sometimes happens that definable groups relative to a theory $T$ correspond to groups of classical interest in mathematics, e.g. as you mention in the question, definable groups relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields are essentially the same as algebraic groups.


  2. Stable groups and their generalizations. One of the most successful applications of Shelah's general stability theory has been the theory of stable groups (i.e. groups definable in stable theories). Model theorists love to generalize results, so there's a natural motivation to try to prove theorems analogous to theorems about stable groups in a wide variety of more general model theoretic contexts, or in individual (unstable) theories of interest. Extra motivation comes from the fact that the theory of stable groups, together with the kinds of connections between definable groups and groups in algebraic geometry mentioned in the previous point, led to Hrushovski's impressive applications of model theory to Mordell-Lang and related problems. This is just one example of applications of the theory of definable groups to other areas of mathematics. For others, you could look at Hrushovski's work on approximate groups, or recent applications to regularity lemmas in groups - both of these make heavy use of theorems about definable groups outside the stable context which were inspired by theorems about stable groups.


  3. Binding groups and internality. Getting more technical here, internality is a key concept in geometric stability theory. Roughly speaking, if one (type-)definable set $X$ is internal to another (type-)definable set $Y$, then the automorphism group of $X$ over $Y$ in the monster model is realizable as a definable group, called the binding group. The classic example is that an $n$-dimensional vector space $V$ over $k$ is internal to the field $k$, with binding group $text{GL}_n(k)$. If you can understand what kinds of groups are definable in your theory, then you can understand what kinds of internality relations are possible relative to your theory, which can lead to powerful structural results.





Edit: In the comments, you ask "Why not study definable lattices, or rings, or whatever?" In fact, model theorists do study such things. Classifying definable equivalence relations (elimination of imaginaries) is extremely important - it's one of the first things you want to do when you start studying a theory. It's also very important to know whether your theory has any definable orders. And the question of the definability of a field in certain structures is the central question of the Zilber trichotomy and Zariski geometries, which has been a central motivating force in modern model theory.



My point is that definable groups get more attention than other kinds of structures (like lattices, for example) for reasons including those I outlined above. But a huge variety of instances of the general question of interpretability of certain theories in other theories come up everywhere in model theory.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 19:13












  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 20:02










  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 20:04











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "504"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f322883%2fwhy-are-model-theorists-so-fond-of-definable-groups%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes









11












$begingroup$

Here are a few reasons. These are just my perspectives - some people may disagree, and I'm sure there are good reasons to study definable groups that I'm missing.




  1. Mathematicians in general are fond of groups. There is a general theme in mathematics (with different motivations in different contexts) of developing a theory of group objects in any category of interest. For example, algebraic groups are group objects in the category of algebraic varieties, Lie groups are group objects in the category of differentiable manifolds, topological groups are group objects in the category of topological spaces, etc. Model theorists study the category of definable sets relative to a first-order theory, and group objects in this category are definable groups. [Aside: I'm confused by your comment "model theory is not mainly about definable things in my opinion". If it's not about definable things, what is it about?] Moreover, it sometimes happens that definable groups relative to a theory $T$ correspond to groups of classical interest in mathematics, e.g. as you mention in the question, definable groups relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields are essentially the same as algebraic groups.


  2. Stable groups and their generalizations. One of the most successful applications of Shelah's general stability theory has been the theory of stable groups (i.e. groups definable in stable theories). Model theorists love to generalize results, so there's a natural motivation to try to prove theorems analogous to theorems about stable groups in a wide variety of more general model theoretic contexts, or in individual (unstable) theories of interest. Extra motivation comes from the fact that the theory of stable groups, together with the kinds of connections between definable groups and groups in algebraic geometry mentioned in the previous point, led to Hrushovski's impressive applications of model theory to Mordell-Lang and related problems. This is just one example of applications of the theory of definable groups to other areas of mathematics. For others, you could look at Hrushovski's work on approximate groups, or recent applications to regularity lemmas in groups - both of these make heavy use of theorems about definable groups outside the stable context which were inspired by theorems about stable groups.


  3. Binding groups and internality. Getting more technical here, internality is a key concept in geometric stability theory. Roughly speaking, if one (type-)definable set $X$ is internal to another (type-)definable set $Y$, then the automorphism group of $X$ over $Y$ in the monster model is realizable as a definable group, called the binding group. The classic example is that an $n$-dimensional vector space $V$ over $k$ is internal to the field $k$, with binding group $text{GL}_n(k)$. If you can understand what kinds of groups are definable in your theory, then you can understand what kinds of internality relations are possible relative to your theory, which can lead to powerful structural results.





Edit: In the comments, you ask "Why not study definable lattices, or rings, or whatever?" In fact, model theorists do study such things. Classifying definable equivalence relations (elimination of imaginaries) is extremely important - it's one of the first things you want to do when you start studying a theory. It's also very important to know whether your theory has any definable orders. And the question of the definability of a field in certain structures is the central question of the Zilber trichotomy and Zariski geometries, which has been a central motivating force in modern model theory.



My point is that definable groups get more attention than other kinds of structures (like lattices, for example) for reasons including those I outlined above. But a huge variety of instances of the general question of interpretability of certain theories in other theories come up everywhere in model theory.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 19:13












  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 20:02










  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 20:04
















11












$begingroup$

Here are a few reasons. These are just my perspectives - some people may disagree, and I'm sure there are good reasons to study definable groups that I'm missing.




  1. Mathematicians in general are fond of groups. There is a general theme in mathematics (with different motivations in different contexts) of developing a theory of group objects in any category of interest. For example, algebraic groups are group objects in the category of algebraic varieties, Lie groups are group objects in the category of differentiable manifolds, topological groups are group objects in the category of topological spaces, etc. Model theorists study the category of definable sets relative to a first-order theory, and group objects in this category are definable groups. [Aside: I'm confused by your comment "model theory is not mainly about definable things in my opinion". If it's not about definable things, what is it about?] Moreover, it sometimes happens that definable groups relative to a theory $T$ correspond to groups of classical interest in mathematics, e.g. as you mention in the question, definable groups relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields are essentially the same as algebraic groups.


  2. Stable groups and their generalizations. One of the most successful applications of Shelah's general stability theory has been the theory of stable groups (i.e. groups definable in stable theories). Model theorists love to generalize results, so there's a natural motivation to try to prove theorems analogous to theorems about stable groups in a wide variety of more general model theoretic contexts, or in individual (unstable) theories of interest. Extra motivation comes from the fact that the theory of stable groups, together with the kinds of connections between definable groups and groups in algebraic geometry mentioned in the previous point, led to Hrushovski's impressive applications of model theory to Mordell-Lang and related problems. This is just one example of applications of the theory of definable groups to other areas of mathematics. For others, you could look at Hrushovski's work on approximate groups, or recent applications to regularity lemmas in groups - both of these make heavy use of theorems about definable groups outside the stable context which were inspired by theorems about stable groups.


  3. Binding groups and internality. Getting more technical here, internality is a key concept in geometric stability theory. Roughly speaking, if one (type-)definable set $X$ is internal to another (type-)definable set $Y$, then the automorphism group of $X$ over $Y$ in the monster model is realizable as a definable group, called the binding group. The classic example is that an $n$-dimensional vector space $V$ over $k$ is internal to the field $k$, with binding group $text{GL}_n(k)$. If you can understand what kinds of groups are definable in your theory, then you can understand what kinds of internality relations are possible relative to your theory, which can lead to powerful structural results.





Edit: In the comments, you ask "Why not study definable lattices, or rings, or whatever?" In fact, model theorists do study such things. Classifying definable equivalence relations (elimination of imaginaries) is extremely important - it's one of the first things you want to do when you start studying a theory. It's also very important to know whether your theory has any definable orders. And the question of the definability of a field in certain structures is the central question of the Zilber trichotomy and Zariski geometries, which has been a central motivating force in modern model theory.



My point is that definable groups get more attention than other kinds of structures (like lattices, for example) for reasons including those I outlined above. But a huge variety of instances of the general question of interpretability of certain theories in other theories come up everywhere in model theory.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 19:13












  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 20:02










  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 20:04














11












11








11





$begingroup$

Here are a few reasons. These are just my perspectives - some people may disagree, and I'm sure there are good reasons to study definable groups that I'm missing.




  1. Mathematicians in general are fond of groups. There is a general theme in mathematics (with different motivations in different contexts) of developing a theory of group objects in any category of interest. For example, algebraic groups are group objects in the category of algebraic varieties, Lie groups are group objects in the category of differentiable manifolds, topological groups are group objects in the category of topological spaces, etc. Model theorists study the category of definable sets relative to a first-order theory, and group objects in this category are definable groups. [Aside: I'm confused by your comment "model theory is not mainly about definable things in my opinion". If it's not about definable things, what is it about?] Moreover, it sometimes happens that definable groups relative to a theory $T$ correspond to groups of classical interest in mathematics, e.g. as you mention in the question, definable groups relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields are essentially the same as algebraic groups.


  2. Stable groups and their generalizations. One of the most successful applications of Shelah's general stability theory has been the theory of stable groups (i.e. groups definable in stable theories). Model theorists love to generalize results, so there's a natural motivation to try to prove theorems analogous to theorems about stable groups in a wide variety of more general model theoretic contexts, or in individual (unstable) theories of interest. Extra motivation comes from the fact that the theory of stable groups, together with the kinds of connections between definable groups and groups in algebraic geometry mentioned in the previous point, led to Hrushovski's impressive applications of model theory to Mordell-Lang and related problems. This is just one example of applications of the theory of definable groups to other areas of mathematics. For others, you could look at Hrushovski's work on approximate groups, or recent applications to regularity lemmas in groups - both of these make heavy use of theorems about definable groups outside the stable context which were inspired by theorems about stable groups.


  3. Binding groups and internality. Getting more technical here, internality is a key concept in geometric stability theory. Roughly speaking, if one (type-)definable set $X$ is internal to another (type-)definable set $Y$, then the automorphism group of $X$ over $Y$ in the monster model is realizable as a definable group, called the binding group. The classic example is that an $n$-dimensional vector space $V$ over $k$ is internal to the field $k$, with binding group $text{GL}_n(k)$. If you can understand what kinds of groups are definable in your theory, then you can understand what kinds of internality relations are possible relative to your theory, which can lead to powerful structural results.





Edit: In the comments, you ask "Why not study definable lattices, or rings, or whatever?" In fact, model theorists do study such things. Classifying definable equivalence relations (elimination of imaginaries) is extremely important - it's one of the first things you want to do when you start studying a theory. It's also very important to know whether your theory has any definable orders. And the question of the definability of a field in certain structures is the central question of the Zilber trichotomy and Zariski geometries, which has been a central motivating force in modern model theory.



My point is that definable groups get more attention than other kinds of structures (like lattices, for example) for reasons including those I outlined above. But a huge variety of instances of the general question of interpretability of certain theories in other theories come up everywhere in model theory.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$



Here are a few reasons. These are just my perspectives - some people may disagree, and I'm sure there are good reasons to study definable groups that I'm missing.




  1. Mathematicians in general are fond of groups. There is a general theme in mathematics (with different motivations in different contexts) of developing a theory of group objects in any category of interest. For example, algebraic groups are group objects in the category of algebraic varieties, Lie groups are group objects in the category of differentiable manifolds, topological groups are group objects in the category of topological spaces, etc. Model theorists study the category of definable sets relative to a first-order theory, and group objects in this category are definable groups. [Aside: I'm confused by your comment "model theory is not mainly about definable things in my opinion". If it's not about definable things, what is it about?] Moreover, it sometimes happens that definable groups relative to a theory $T$ correspond to groups of classical interest in mathematics, e.g. as you mention in the question, definable groups relative to the theory of algebraically closed fields are essentially the same as algebraic groups.


  2. Stable groups and their generalizations. One of the most successful applications of Shelah's general stability theory has been the theory of stable groups (i.e. groups definable in stable theories). Model theorists love to generalize results, so there's a natural motivation to try to prove theorems analogous to theorems about stable groups in a wide variety of more general model theoretic contexts, or in individual (unstable) theories of interest. Extra motivation comes from the fact that the theory of stable groups, together with the kinds of connections between definable groups and groups in algebraic geometry mentioned in the previous point, led to Hrushovski's impressive applications of model theory to Mordell-Lang and related problems. This is just one example of applications of the theory of definable groups to other areas of mathematics. For others, you could look at Hrushovski's work on approximate groups, or recent applications to regularity lemmas in groups - both of these make heavy use of theorems about definable groups outside the stable context which were inspired by theorems about stable groups.


  3. Binding groups and internality. Getting more technical here, internality is a key concept in geometric stability theory. Roughly speaking, if one (type-)definable set $X$ is internal to another (type-)definable set $Y$, then the automorphism group of $X$ over $Y$ in the monster model is realizable as a definable group, called the binding group. The classic example is that an $n$-dimensional vector space $V$ over $k$ is internal to the field $k$, with binding group $text{GL}_n(k)$. If you can understand what kinds of groups are definable in your theory, then you can understand what kinds of internality relations are possible relative to your theory, which can lead to powerful structural results.





Edit: In the comments, you ask "Why not study definable lattices, or rings, or whatever?" In fact, model theorists do study such things. Classifying definable equivalence relations (elimination of imaginaries) is extremely important - it's one of the first things you want to do when you start studying a theory. It's also very important to know whether your theory has any definable orders. And the question of the definability of a field in certain structures is the central question of the Zilber trichotomy and Zariski geometries, which has been a central motivating force in modern model theory.



My point is that definable groups get more attention than other kinds of structures (like lattices, for example) for reasons including those I outlined above. But a huge variety of instances of the general question of interpretability of certain theories in other theories come up everywhere in model theory.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited Feb 10 at 17:33

























answered Feb 10 at 17:13









Alex KruckmanAlex Kruckman

1,85911215




1,85911215












  • $begingroup$
    About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 19:13












  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 20:02










  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 20:04


















  • $begingroup$
    About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 19:13












  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 19:53












  • $begingroup$
    Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
    $endgroup$
    – tomasz
    Feb 10 at 20:02










  • $begingroup$
    @tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Kruckman
    Feb 10 at 20:04
















$begingroup$
About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
$endgroup$
– tomasz
Feb 10 at 19:13






$begingroup$
About your aside: from my perspective, model theory is about invariant things. When you go outside of stability theory (well, maybe also outside of $omega$-categorical), definable things go near-extinct fast. They are still important, but often they don't really get to the heart of things.
$endgroup$
– tomasz
Feb 10 at 19:13














$begingroup$
@tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 19:53






$begingroup$
@tomasz Yeah, that's a totally reasonable point of view. I think you can come at it from either side: If you're primarily interested in the invariant category, you should still care about definability, because definable / type-definable / $bigvee$-definable / Borel-definable sets have better properties (like compactness!). On the other hand, to me, the definable category is the main object of interest, and one is naturally led to enlarge the category by invariant gadgets (this is essentially what Stone duality teaches us) in order to prove things about definable sets.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 19:53














$begingroup$
I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 19:53






$begingroup$
I guess I'm just too attached to the compactness theorem to agree that model theory is primarily about invariant things.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 19:53














$begingroup$
Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
$endgroup$
– tomasz
Feb 10 at 20:02




$begingroup$
Well, with type-definable, you still have compactness, you just need to be careful with negations.
$endgroup$
– tomasz
Feb 10 at 20:02












$begingroup$
@tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 20:04




$begingroup$
@tomasz Oh, absolutely. That's why type-definability is the best kind of invariance after definability.
$endgroup$
– Alex Kruckman
Feb 10 at 20:04


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to MathOverflow!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f322883%2fwhy-are-model-theorists-so-fond-of-definable-groups%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

Probability when a professor distributes a quiz and homework assignment to a class of n students.

Aardman Animations

Are they similar matrix