What is a minimal set of rules that determine the usual order on $Bbb{N}$ given that $1 lt p_1 lt p_2 lt...
$begingroup$
Let $p_i$ always mean the $i$th prime number.
Given two numbers $a, b in Bbb{N}$ in the form $a = {(p_i, e_i) : p_i^{e_i} mid a, e_i text{ maximal}}$ ie. essentially their unique factorization, what is a natural way to compute whether $a gt b$?
For instance a rule might be $p_{j}^2 gt p_{j+1}$ always. So that given $a = 2^2$, $b = 3$, we immediately have $a gt b$.
Is there a simple set of rules such that given the usual ordering on the primes and $1$: $1 lt p_1 lt p_2 lt dots$ we can always derive $a gt b$ when it is true?
By no means can we include converting the number to a base representation and comparing the last digit.
It's best to work by example sometimes. Take $2 cdot 7 lt 3cdot 5$. Well, $2 lt 3 lt 5 lt 7$ so... ?
I'm stuck on this one, what is the simplest rule you can think of to overcome this example?
elementary-number-theory prime-numbers order-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $p_i$ always mean the $i$th prime number.
Given two numbers $a, b in Bbb{N}$ in the form $a = {(p_i, e_i) : p_i^{e_i} mid a, e_i text{ maximal}}$ ie. essentially their unique factorization, what is a natural way to compute whether $a gt b$?
For instance a rule might be $p_{j}^2 gt p_{j+1}$ always. So that given $a = 2^2$, $b = 3$, we immediately have $a gt b$.
Is there a simple set of rules such that given the usual ordering on the primes and $1$: $1 lt p_1 lt p_2 lt dots$ we can always derive $a gt b$ when it is true?
By no means can we include converting the number to a base representation and comparing the last digit.
It's best to work by example sometimes. Take $2 cdot 7 lt 3cdot 5$. Well, $2 lt 3 lt 5 lt 7$ so... ?
I'm stuck on this one, what is the simplest rule you can think of to overcome this example?
elementary-number-theory prime-numbers order-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
2
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
1
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $p_i$ always mean the $i$th prime number.
Given two numbers $a, b in Bbb{N}$ in the form $a = {(p_i, e_i) : p_i^{e_i} mid a, e_i text{ maximal}}$ ie. essentially their unique factorization, what is a natural way to compute whether $a gt b$?
For instance a rule might be $p_{j}^2 gt p_{j+1}$ always. So that given $a = 2^2$, $b = 3$, we immediately have $a gt b$.
Is there a simple set of rules such that given the usual ordering on the primes and $1$: $1 lt p_1 lt p_2 lt dots$ we can always derive $a gt b$ when it is true?
By no means can we include converting the number to a base representation and comparing the last digit.
It's best to work by example sometimes. Take $2 cdot 7 lt 3cdot 5$. Well, $2 lt 3 lt 5 lt 7$ so... ?
I'm stuck on this one, what is the simplest rule you can think of to overcome this example?
elementary-number-theory prime-numbers order-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
Let $p_i$ always mean the $i$th prime number.
Given two numbers $a, b in Bbb{N}$ in the form $a = {(p_i, e_i) : p_i^{e_i} mid a, e_i text{ maximal}}$ ie. essentially their unique factorization, what is a natural way to compute whether $a gt b$?
For instance a rule might be $p_{j}^2 gt p_{j+1}$ always. So that given $a = 2^2$, $b = 3$, we immediately have $a gt b$.
Is there a simple set of rules such that given the usual ordering on the primes and $1$: $1 lt p_1 lt p_2 lt dots$ we can always derive $a gt b$ when it is true?
By no means can we include converting the number to a base representation and comparing the last digit.
It's best to work by example sometimes. Take $2 cdot 7 lt 3cdot 5$. Well, $2 lt 3 lt 5 lt 7$ so... ?
I'm stuck on this one, what is the simplest rule you can think of to overcome this example?
elementary-number-theory prime-numbers order-theory natural-numbers
elementary-number-theory prime-numbers order-theory natural-numbers
edited Dec 20 '18 at 5:01
BananaCats
asked Dec 20 '18 at 4:55
BananaCatsBananaCats
9,26252558
9,26252558
2
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
1
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39
add a comment |
2
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
1
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39
2
2
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
1
1
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39
add a comment |
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Here's some evidence that this may be hard.
In mathematical logic class we learn that the theory of $(mathbb N,times)$ is decidable. Basically, because the fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that the monoid of positive integers under multiplication $times$ is a free commutative monoid on an infinite set of generators, the prime numbers.
But if we add in the relation $x< y$, you get the same definable sets as in all of first-order arithmetic $(mathbb N,+,times)$, which is not decidable. This is described by Alexis Bès.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3047172%2fwhat-is-a-minimal-set-of-rules-that-determine-the-usual-order-on-bbbn-given%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Here's some evidence that this may be hard.
In mathematical logic class we learn that the theory of $(mathbb N,times)$ is decidable. Basically, because the fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that the monoid of positive integers under multiplication $times$ is a free commutative monoid on an infinite set of generators, the prime numbers.
But if we add in the relation $x< y$, you get the same definable sets as in all of first-order arithmetic $(mathbb N,+,times)$, which is not decidable. This is described by Alexis Bès.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's some evidence that this may be hard.
In mathematical logic class we learn that the theory of $(mathbb N,times)$ is decidable. Basically, because the fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that the monoid of positive integers under multiplication $times$ is a free commutative monoid on an infinite set of generators, the prime numbers.
But if we add in the relation $x< y$, you get the same definable sets as in all of first-order arithmetic $(mathbb N,+,times)$, which is not decidable. This is described by Alexis Bès.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Here's some evidence that this may be hard.
In mathematical logic class we learn that the theory of $(mathbb N,times)$ is decidable. Basically, because the fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that the monoid of positive integers under multiplication $times$ is a free commutative monoid on an infinite set of generators, the prime numbers.
But if we add in the relation $x< y$, you get the same definable sets as in all of first-order arithmetic $(mathbb N,+,times)$, which is not decidable. This is described by Alexis Bès.
$endgroup$
Here's some evidence that this may be hard.
In mathematical logic class we learn that the theory of $(mathbb N,times)$ is decidable. Basically, because the fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that the monoid of positive integers under multiplication $times$ is a free commutative monoid on an infinite set of generators, the prime numbers.
But if we add in the relation $x< y$, you get the same definable sets as in all of first-order arithmetic $(mathbb N,+,times)$, which is not decidable. This is described by Alexis Bès.
answered Dec 20 '18 at 5:40
Bjørn Kjos-HanssenBjørn Kjos-Hanssen
2,097918
2,097918
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3047172%2fwhat-is-a-minimal-set-of-rules-that-determine-the-usual-order-on-bbbn-given%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
2
$begingroup$
It's certainly true that, given only the information $p_1<p_2<p_3<p_4$, there's no way to determine which of $p_1p_4$ and $p_2p_3$ is larger.
$endgroup$
– Greg Martin
Dec 20 '18 at 5:31
1
$begingroup$
Or how about comparing $2^{11}3^25^97$ with $p_{10 000 000 000}?$ I don't expect there to be a simple rule.
$endgroup$
– Ross Millikan
Dec 20 '18 at 5:39