Is there a way to prove numbers irrational in general?












0












$begingroup$


I'm familiar with the typical proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$, where we assume it is equivalent to $frac ab$ for some integers $a,b$, then prove that both $a$ and $b$ are divisible by $2$, repeat infinitely, proof by contradiction, QED. I'm also familiar with the fact that if you repeat this procedure for any radical, you can similarly prove that each $a^n,b^n$ are divisible by the radicand, where $n$ is the root of the radical (though things get tricky if you don't reduce first). In other words, the proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$ generalizes to prove that any number of the form $sqrt[m]{n}notinmathbb{Q}$.



Further, since adding or multiplying a rational and an irrational yields an irrational, this is a proof for all algebraic irrationals. (Ex. I can prove $phi=frac{1+sqrt5}{2}$ irrational just by demonstrating that the $sqrt5$ term is irrational.)



Because this relies on the algebra of radicals, this won't help for transcendental numbers. Is there a proof that generalizes to all irrational numbers, or must each transcendental number be proven irrational independently?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:32










  • $begingroup$
    @Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
    $endgroup$
    – DonielF
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38










  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
    $endgroup$
    – J.G.
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:39












  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 26 '18 at 3:29
















0












$begingroup$


I'm familiar with the typical proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$, where we assume it is equivalent to $frac ab$ for some integers $a,b$, then prove that both $a$ and $b$ are divisible by $2$, repeat infinitely, proof by contradiction, QED. I'm also familiar with the fact that if you repeat this procedure for any radical, you can similarly prove that each $a^n,b^n$ are divisible by the radicand, where $n$ is the root of the radical (though things get tricky if you don't reduce first). In other words, the proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$ generalizes to prove that any number of the form $sqrt[m]{n}notinmathbb{Q}$.



Further, since adding or multiplying a rational and an irrational yields an irrational, this is a proof for all algebraic irrationals. (Ex. I can prove $phi=frac{1+sqrt5}{2}$ irrational just by demonstrating that the $sqrt5$ term is irrational.)



Because this relies on the algebra of radicals, this won't help for transcendental numbers. Is there a proof that generalizes to all irrational numbers, or must each transcendental number be proven irrational independently?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:32










  • $begingroup$
    @Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
    $endgroup$
    – DonielF
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38










  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
    $endgroup$
    – J.G.
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:39












  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 26 '18 at 3:29














0












0








0





$begingroup$


I'm familiar with the typical proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$, where we assume it is equivalent to $frac ab$ for some integers $a,b$, then prove that both $a$ and $b$ are divisible by $2$, repeat infinitely, proof by contradiction, QED. I'm also familiar with the fact that if you repeat this procedure for any radical, you can similarly prove that each $a^n,b^n$ are divisible by the radicand, where $n$ is the root of the radical (though things get tricky if you don't reduce first). In other words, the proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$ generalizes to prove that any number of the form $sqrt[m]{n}notinmathbb{Q}$.



Further, since adding or multiplying a rational and an irrational yields an irrational, this is a proof for all algebraic irrationals. (Ex. I can prove $phi=frac{1+sqrt5}{2}$ irrational just by demonstrating that the $sqrt5$ term is irrational.)



Because this relies on the algebra of radicals, this won't help for transcendental numbers. Is there a proof that generalizes to all irrational numbers, or must each transcendental number be proven irrational independently?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I'm familiar with the typical proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$, where we assume it is equivalent to $frac ab$ for some integers $a,b$, then prove that both $a$ and $b$ are divisible by $2$, repeat infinitely, proof by contradiction, QED. I'm also familiar with the fact that if you repeat this procedure for any radical, you can similarly prove that each $a^n,b^n$ are divisible by the radicand, where $n$ is the root of the radical (though things get tricky if you don't reduce first). In other words, the proof that $sqrt2notinmathbb{Q}$ generalizes to prove that any number of the form $sqrt[m]{n}notinmathbb{Q}$.



Further, since adding or multiplying a rational and an irrational yields an irrational, this is a proof for all algebraic irrationals. (Ex. I can prove $phi=frac{1+sqrt5}{2}$ irrational just by demonstrating that the $sqrt5$ term is irrational.)



Because this relies on the algebra of radicals, this won't help for transcendental numbers. Is there a proof that generalizes to all irrational numbers, or must each transcendental number be proven irrational independently?







rationality-testing






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 25 '18 at 19:29









DonielFDonielF

515515




515515








  • 3




    $begingroup$
    This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:32










  • $begingroup$
    @Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
    $endgroup$
    – DonielF
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38










  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
    $endgroup$
    – J.G.
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:39












  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 26 '18 at 3:29














  • 3




    $begingroup$
    This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:32










  • $begingroup$
    @Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
    $endgroup$
    – DonielF
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38










  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
    $endgroup$
    – Noah Schweber
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:38






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
    $endgroup$
    – J.G.
    Dec 25 '18 at 19:39












  • $begingroup$
    @DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
    $endgroup$
    – Steven Stadnicki
    Dec 26 '18 at 3:29








3




3




$begingroup$
This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Dec 25 '18 at 19:32




$begingroup$
This may sound like silly pedantry, but what is your definition of 'number'? For instance, what (if anything) prevents 'the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt{2}$ if it's false' from being a valid number under your definition?
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Dec 25 '18 at 19:32












$begingroup$
@Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
$endgroup$
– DonielF
Dec 25 '18 at 19:38




$begingroup$
@Steven Imagine a line which stretches infinitely in both directions, and we pick an arbitrary point on it to label 0. Let's define a number as an unmovable point on this line, and the number's value is determined by its distance from the point we labeled 0. The reason "the number which is 1 if Goldbach's conjecture is true and $sqrt2$ if it's false" is not a number is because it's not a fixed point; it's in a superposition of "conjecture is true" and "conjecture is false" (for lack of a better term) and therefore occupies multiple points on the line.
$endgroup$
– DonielF
Dec 25 '18 at 19:38












$begingroup$
@DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Dec 25 '18 at 19:38




$begingroup$
@DonielF No, it's a completely fixed point - it's either $1$ or $sqrt{2}$, we just don't currently (and may never) now which it is.
$endgroup$
– Noah Schweber
Dec 25 '18 at 19:38




3




3




$begingroup$
Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
$endgroup$
– J.G.
Dec 25 '18 at 19:39






$begingroup$
Not all algebraic numbers admit the radical form you assume them to in your attempted proof all algebraic numbers' rationality is decidable this way. For example, quintics' roots don't in general take such a form.
$endgroup$
– J.G.
Dec 25 '18 at 19:39














$begingroup$
@DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Dec 26 '18 at 3:29




$begingroup$
@DonielF For another perspective, 'its distance from the point labeled 0' is just a circular definition; you're defining the number in terms of itself. Indeed, the overwhelming majority of real numbers have no finite definition (this is a nice little exercise in infinite counting) and so the very notion of an irrationality proof for them needs a little unwinding. (Of course, all of the numbers that don't have a finite definition are immediately irrational by contradiction, but).
$endgroup$
– Steven Stadnicki
Dec 26 '18 at 3:29










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes


















6












$begingroup$

There is no known general method of dealing with this problem. Otherwise, we would already know whether or not the Euler–Mascheroni constant is rational.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3052372%2fis-there-a-way-to-prove-numbers-irrational-in-general%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes








    1 Answer
    1






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    6












    $begingroup$

    There is no known general method of dealing with this problem. Otherwise, we would already know whether or not the Euler–Mascheroni constant is rational.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      6












      $begingroup$

      There is no known general method of dealing with this problem. Otherwise, we would already know whether or not the Euler–Mascheroni constant is rational.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        6












        6








        6





        $begingroup$

        There is no known general method of dealing with this problem. Otherwise, we would already know whether or not the Euler–Mascheroni constant is rational.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        There is no known general method of dealing with this problem. Otherwise, we would already know whether or not the Euler–Mascheroni constant is rational.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Dec 25 '18 at 19:38









        José Carlos SantosJosé Carlos Santos

        167k22132235




        167k22132235






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3052372%2fis-there-a-way-to-prove-numbers-irrational-in-general%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            How do I know what Microsoft account the skydrive app is syncing to?

            Grease: Live!

            When does type information flow backwards in C++?